General Actions:
Tournament | Round | Opponent | Judge | Cites | Round Report | Open Source | Edit/Delete |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
CPS | Doubles | Srikar Pyda | Panel |
| |||
CPS | 1 | X | X |
| |||
CPS | 1 | X | X |
| |||
Direct Payments CP | 1 | x | x |
| |||
UPS | 1 | X | X |
| |||
UPS | 1 | x | x |
| |||
all of em | 1 | everyone | anyone |
| |||
anything jan feb | 1 | x | x |
| |||
anything jan feb | 1 | x | x |
| |||
anything jan feb | 2 | x | x |
| |||
berk | 1 | x | x |
| |||
berk | Doubles | The Walia Man | Shmikler, Fink, Fried |
| |||
berk | Triples | Bellarmine CP HS | McNally, Mills, Bower |
| |||
berk | Doubles | The Walia Man | Shmikler, Fried, Fink |
| |||
berkeley | 1 | x | x |
| |||
lol | 1 | no | clue |
| |||
no clue | 1 | uhh | idk |
| |||
stanford | 9 | nobody i think | nobody i think |
| |||
stanford | 1 | x | x |
| |||
stanford | 9 | x | x |
| |||
stanford and berkeley | 2 | x | x |
| |||
stanford and berkeley | 1 | x | x |
| |||
ups | 6 | x | x |
| |||
ups | 6 | x | x |
| |||
ups | 8 | x | x |
| |||
ups | 5 | x | x |
| |||
x | 1 | x | x |
|
Tournament | Round | Report |
---|---|---|
berk | Triples | Opponent: Bellarmine CP HS | Judge: McNally, Mills, Bower AC - Cap K aff Decision Neg on theory and impact turn to aff |
berk | Doubles | Opponent: The Walia Man | Judge: Shmikler, Fried, Fink AC - Community Based Forestry plan |
To modify or delete round reports, edit the associated round.
Entry | Date |
---|---|
A2 CapTournament: UPS | Round: 1 | Opponent: x | Judge: x
Indeed, and this is the argument we wish to make in this book, the project of understanding the beast has itself produced a beast, or even a bestiary; and the process of producing knowledge in service to politics has estranged rather than united understanding and action. Bringing these together again, or allowing them to touch in different ways, is one of our motivating aspirations. “Capitalism” occupies a special and privileged place in the language of social representation. References to “capitalist society” are a common¬place of left and even mainstream social description, as are references — to the market, to the global economy, to postindustrial society — in which an unnamed capitalism is implicitly invoked as the defining and unifying moment of a complex economic and social formation. Just as the economic system in eastern Europe used confidently to be described as communist or socialist, so a general confidence in economic classification characterizes representations of an increasingly capitalist world system. But what might be seen as the grounds of this confidence, if we put aside notions of “reality” as the authentic origin of its representations? Why might it seem problematic to say that the United States is a Christian nation, or a heterosexual one, despite the widespread belief that Christianity and heterosexuality are dominant or majority practices in their respective domains, while at the same time it seems legitimate and indeed “accurate” to say that the US is a capitalist country?1 What is it about the former expressions, and their critical history, that makes them visible as “regulatory fictions,”2 ways of erasing or obscuring difference, while the latter is seen as accurate representation? Why, moreover, have embracing and holistic expressions for social struc¬ture like patriarchy fallen into relative disuse among feminist theorists (see Pringle 1995; Barrett and Phillips 1992) while similar concep¬tions of capitalism as a system or “structure of power” are still preva¬lent and resilient? These sorts of questions, by virtue of their scarcity and scant claims to legitimacy, have provided us a motive for this book.3 The End of Capitalism (As We Knew It) problematizes “capitalism”. as an economic and social descriptor.4 Scrutinizing what might be seen as throwaway uses of the term — passing references, for example, to the capitalist system or to global capitalism — as well as systematic and deliberate attempts to represent capitalism as a central and organizing feature of modern social experience, the book selectively traces the discursive origins of a widespread understanding: that capitalism is the hegemonic. or even the only, present form of economy and that it will continue to be so in the proximate future. It follows from this prevalent though not ubiquitous view that noncapitalist economic sites, if they exist at all, must inhabit the social margins; and, as a corollary, that deliberate attempts to develop noncapitalist economic practices and institutions must take place in the social interstices, in the realm of experiment, or in a visionary space of revolutionary social replacement. Representations of capitalism are a potent constituent of the anticapi¬talist imagination, providing images of what is to be resisted and changed as well as intimations of the strategies, techniques, and possibilities of changing it. For this reason, depictions of “capitalist hegemony” deserve a particularly skeptical reading. For in the vicinity of these representations, the very idea of a noncapitalist economy takes the shape of an unlikelihood or even an impossibility. It becomes difficult to entertain a vision of the prevalence and vitality of noncapitalist economic forms, or of daily or partial replacements of capitalism by noncapitalist economic practices, or of capitalist retreats and reversals. In this sense, “capitalist hegemony” operates not only as a constituent of, but also as a brake upon, the anticapitalist imagination.5 What difference might it make to release that brake and allow an anticapitalist economic imaginary to develop unrestricted?6 If we were to dissolve the image that looms in the economic foreground, what shadowy economic forms might come forward? In these questions we can identify the broad outlines of our project: to discover or create a world of economic difference, and to populate that world with exotic creatures that become, upon inspection, quite local and familiar (not to mention familiar beings that are not what they seem). 2. TURN, ecological destruction is the consequence of the absence of capitalism – that's radical socialism. Lewis But as Theodore Hamerow’s (1990) masterful account of the “graying of the revolution” makes abundantly clear, the rise of the bureaucratic oligarchy may have been unintended but it was nonetheless inexorable. If eco-marxists were ever to gain power in the United States, we could expect history to recapitulate itself on this score. Still, Marxist apologists will continue to inform us that communist leaders just made a few critical errors, and that if we were once again to begin building communism, this time we could get it right. This position might be reasonable had the world known only a single Marxist state, but the sad fact is that the experiment has been just as disastrous on every occasion and in every social environment in which it has been attempted. Scholars seeking real material and structural explanations in history would be forced to admit that marxism’s political failure has been rather more unavoidable than accidental. 3. Their impact story is empirically denied -- capitalism has empowered human rights with its concern for human worth. Berger writes, “A third very important charge brought against capitalism is that it is supposedly linked with political oppression. The critiques of capitalism habitually contrast the political oppressiveness of capitalist systems with the alleged socialist linkage with liberation of one sort or another. The root facts again are very interesting. If one speaks of democracy as being distinguished from regimes of political oppression, there is not a single case in the world of a society which one could reasonably call socialist which is a democracy. There are no socialist democracies. All the democracies in the world are states that are part of the international capitalist system. There is a large number of capitalist non-democratic states. In other words, the distribution of facts have a certain formal analogy to the distribution of success stories noted above. What it suggests, at least hypothetically, is that capitalism, while clearly not a sufficient condition for economic success, seems to be a necessary condition. In the same way, just as capitalism clearly cannot be identified with democracy (otherwise one could not explain the cases of capitalist societies with no democracy), there seems to be a propensity of capitalist systems toward democracy. Socialism, on the other hand, shows a very clear propensity in the other direction. This is no great mystery, but can be systematically analyzed in terms of the political implication of economies that are largely allocative, as against market-oriented, in organization. This Is not to espouse the Wilsonian view, for I do not believe that democracy is the only morally acceptable form of government, although I would personally go to great lengths to defend it in my own country. In my view there are benevolent societies which are not democratic. Leaving aside democracy for a moment for purposes of analysis and looking simply at where one finds the grossest violations of human rights, and where one finds something approximating institutionalized respect for human rights, what one finds is a remarkable correlation between institutions that organize respect for human rights and democracy. Thus, the question of whether capitalism is or is not conducive to democracy is a question very much related to the question of human rights; and if one gives any moral stature to the question of human rights, one must take that correlation very seriously indeed.” K., pen name shared by feminist economic geographers Julie Graham and Katherine Gibson (“The End of Capitalism (As We Knew It): A Feminist Critique of Political Economy”, pg 2-5) Peter Berger, Corporations and the Common Good, 1986, 22-23 | 2/19/14 |
A2 Community Based ForestryTournament: berk | Round: Doubles | Opponent: The Walia Man | Judge: Shmikler, Fried, Fink Community forestry is thought to diffuse the kind of tensions over access to resources that frequently make centralized forest management systems based on the principles of scientific forestry ineffective and conflictive. Centralized systems often create resistance, as communities whose vegetation management practices have been declared illegal by forest bureaucracies anonymously contest the restrictions imposed on them by ‘stealing’ trees and committing ‘arson’. These restrictions are intimately related to the requirements of scientific forestry, however, so co-management strategies relying on scientific forestry might also engender various forms of internal resistance, such as tree theft. Local interpretations of justice in access to resources, together with community social structures and the distribution of resources can result in internalized resistance, rendering community-based resource management ineffective. In a Mexican community case-study, scientific forestry and tree theft co-evolved during a period of concessions and continue under co-management. This system creates an arena where anonymous individual resistance like tree theft can give way to forms of protest more likely to result in legitimate and effective forest management systems. You’re at a huge solvency deficit – the plan doesn’t even work unless actors outside the scope of the aff work. Jong Cornejo (2010), analysing local forestry support initiatives from Peru, Bolivia, Ecuador, and Co- lombia, found that these initiatives in general were duly designed with early involvement of the target beneficiaries, but varied with regard to the meth- ods and intensity used for consultations. The most common operation mode was to organise communal workshops where ideas were presented to target ben- eficiaries asked to provide opinions or suggestions. Even though several initiatives focused on rather new activities among the target beneficiaries, these activi- ties all fit well within the rural producers’ economic strategies. Thus, the new activities proposed by the initiatives did not demand excessive time allocation, consumed only minor amounts of time and thereby occupied a relatively small proportion of the family labour pools. The activities all focused on manag- ing local biodiversity, while complying to the extent possible with the existing regulations. This implied necessarily the introduction of new management practices and new forms of organisation among ru- ral producers. All the cases reviewed by Cornejo (2010) had in common that some kind of intervention by external agents had taken place. Interventions were typically related to a development projects led by a NGO, though government support was also present in sev- eral cases. Despite the fact that important resources had been invested in technical assistance and train- ing, and efforts had been made to define phase-out strategies, an overall result was that few of the in- novations continued after the project finished. One of the reasons was that the initiatives failed to pay sufficient attention to the importance of smallholder business organisation and related capacity-building, and to product value-chain development. Empirically failed in the Amazon and turns your impacts, communities kept doing what they were doing so theres no reason to do the plan -- Jong 2 In contrast to some successful examples from Mexico and Central America, where communal business organisations could be built on existing struc- tures for community and political-legal organisation (Stoian 2005), Amazonian forestry producers had little former integration in market structures and were confronted with entirely new forms of organisation. So, Amazonian forest managers did become only in very few cases direct traders of the raw material or semi-finished products. Most of them continued to sell their products to local intermediaries with little influence on price formation. In fact, they hardly ever succeeded in establishing trust relationships with non-local market participants and therefore did not manage to receive more attractive prices for their products. Findings of a global review of ru- ral community enterprises suggest that the start-up phase necessary to establish viable business struc- tures would take at least between 10–20 years, fol- lowed by a consolidation phase of a similar duration (Donovan et al. 2008). Community Forestry and Tree Theft in Mexico: Resistance or Complicity in Conservation?. Dan Klooster. 2002. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/1467-7660.00155/abstract 16 Opportunities and Challenges for Community forestry: Lessons from Tropical America Convening lead author: Wil de Jong Lead authors: Carlos Cornejo, Pablo Pacheco, Benno Pokorny and Dietmar Stoian Contributing authors: Cesar Sabogal and Bastiaan Louman RegIOnAL exAmpLes Of fOResT ReLATed ChALLenges And OppORTunITIes | 2/19/14 |
A2 Converse TheoryTournament: stanford | Round: 9 | Opponent: x | Judge: x
| 2/19/14 |
A2 NeolibTournament: berk | Round: Triples | Opponent: Bellarmine CP HS | Judge: McNally, Mills, Bower Neo-lib decreases incentive for war Latin America proves anti-neoliberal movements need specific political proposals – the plan alone is doomed to failure because it doesn’t engage the political sphere | 2/19/14 |
Bans Bad TTournament: no clue | Round: 1 | Opponent: uhh | Judge: idk
| 2/18/14 |
Buen Vivir KTournament: ups | Round: 6 | Opponent: x | Judge: x Buen Vivir destroys the value of indigenous life, creating a neo-imperial model that lies about its aims. Walsh 3 And its empirically proven in Ecuador, the lines between Buen Vivir and traditional imperialist development are blurring. Alcoff 2 Development discourse breeds imperialism and oppresses the third world, turns the AC; dooming environmental protection efforts. Berger 12 writes Imperialism leads to unending violence and extinction Eckhardt The alternative is linguistic deconstruction since it's the only way we promote real change. That requires rejection of the aff’s epistemic frame. Kobayashi 94 (Linda, professor of philosophy at Syracuse University, "Mignolo’s Epistemology of Coloniality", The New Centennial Review, Winter 2007, pp. 79-102) (Linda, professor of philosophy at Syracuse University, "Mignolo’s Epistemology of Coloniality", The New Centennial Review, Winter 2007, pp. 79-102) | 2/19/14 |
Buen Vivir TTournament: stanford | Round: 1 | Opponent: x | Judge: x 'Human development' is a concept conceived in the Global North within a design of (international and national) social policy. Buen vivir, roughly translated in English as living well or collective well-being, comes from the cosmologies of the indigenous and African descendent peoples of the South. It is not a policy to be applied but a philosophy to be lived. As such, my first response is to say that there is no relationship. Yet with the incorporation of buen vivir as the transversal axis of the Ecuadorian Constitution in 2008 and as the driving focus of the National Plan of Development in 2009 (also called the National Plan of Buen Vivir), a correlation is beginning to emerge which is I find tension ridden and problematic. In its elaboration as a policy frame, human social development is based on two key principles: the individual and the quality of life. Human social development it can best be described as a new strategy of colonial-imperial design. It is a strategy that portends to insure inclusion and social cohesion and manage ethnic diversity (and its potential threat to state security); a strategy that serves well the interests and needs of the neo-liberal project, now in a more 'humanized' form. Buen vivir, in its most general sense, organizes and constructs a life-system based on the communion of beings (human and otherwise) and nature, C. Standards: The ability to make decisions deriving from discussions, argumentation or debate, is the key skill. It is the one thing every single one of us will do every day of our lives besides breathing. Decision-making transcends boundaries between categories of learning like "policy education"' and "kririk education," it makes irrelevant considerations of whether we will eventually be policymakers, and it transcends questions of what substantive content a debate round should contain. The implication for this analysis is that the critical thinking and argumentative skills offered by real-world decision-making are comparatively greater than any educational disadvantage weighed against them D. Voters – Drop the debater to deter abuse, people aren’t going to read positions they know are abusive. No RVI’s since it would deny the antecedent, which states if abusive vote them down but it doesn't follow that if not abusive vote them up, creating a non sequitor that precludes any RVIs good arguments since arguments have to make logical sense before we consider how they function in round. Use competing interps since IDK what you find reasonable. Vote on Education since it's the only lasting impact of debate AND Fairness since debates a competitive activity theres no point to doing it if one side cant win. HUMAN DEVELOPMENT AND BUEN VIVIR. INTERVIEW WITH CATHERINE WALSH BY DEVELOPMENTPLUS MAR 9, 2010 THE SCOPE OF NEGATIVE FIAT AND THE LOGIC OF DECISION MAKING; L. Pall! Sirait. George Mason University Brett Wallace. George Washington University | 2/19/14 |
Contractarianism NCTournament: CPS | Round: 1 | Opponent: X | Judge: X J. L. Mackie John Leslie Mackie (1917-1981) was a philosopher, originally from Sydney, Australia. From 1967 until his death, he was a fellow of University College, Oxford. He was in 1974 elected a fellow of the British Academy., “Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong” The Subjectivity of Values. The argument from ... limited by subjectivity. Morality is premised on contractual obligations that actors form with each other. Gauthier 1 : Gauthier, David P. Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Clarendon, 1986. Print. Moral principles are ... in their affairs. Thus, the standard is consistency with contractual agreements
2. Developing countries mutually agree with resource extracting companies to allow them to extract resources within the countries because it fulfills the social contract of protecting individuals interests within the nation of allowing economic growth. Luheshi (Natural Resource Extraction Contracts - What Difference Do They Make? Matt Luheshi 9:10, 18 October 2013) The latest in ... oil and gas. 3. Analytic | 1/3/14 |
Death Cult KTournament: stanford and berkeley | Round: 2 | Opponent: x | Judge: x Pursued and censured everywhere, death springs up everywhere again. No longer as apocalyptic folklore, such as might have haunted the living imagination in certain epochs; but voided precisely of any imaginary substance, it passes into the most banal reality, and for us takes on the mask of the very principle of rationality that dominates our lives. Death is when everything functions and serves something else, it is the absolute, signing, cybernetic functionality of the urban environment as in Jacques Tati’s film Play-Time. Man is absolutely indexed on his function, as in Kafka: the age of the civil servant is the age of a culture of death. This is the phantasm of total programming, increased predictability and accuracy, finality not only in material things, but in fulfilling desires. In a word, death is confused with the law of value – and strangely with the structural law of value by which everything is arrested as a coded difference in a universal nexus of relations. This is the true face of ultra-modern death, made up of the faultless, objective, ultra-rapid connection of all the terms in a system. Our true necropolises are no longer the cemeteries, hospitals, wars, hecatombs; death is no longer where we think it is, it is no longer biological, psychological, metaphysical, it is no longer even murder: our societies’ true necropolises are the computer banks or the foyers, blank spaces from which all human noise has been expunged, glass coffins where the world’s sterilized memories are frozen. Only the dead remember everything in something like an immediate eternity of knowledge, a quintessence of the world that today we dream of burying in the form of microfilm and archives, making the entire world into an archive in order that it be discovered by some future civilization. The cryogenic freezing of all knowledge so that it can be resurrected; knowledge passes into immortality as sign-value. Against our dream of losing and forgetting everything, we set up an opposing great wall of relations, connections and information, a dense and inextricable artificial memory, and we bury ourselves alive in the fossilized hope of one day being rediscovered. Computers are the transistorized death to which we submit in the hope of survival. Museums are already there to survive all civilizations, in order to bear testimony. But to what? It is of little importance. The mere fact that they exist testifies that we are in a culture which no longer possesses any meaning for itself and which can now only dream of having meaning for someone else from a later time. Thus everything becomes an environment of death as soon as it is no longer a sign that can be transistorized in a gigantic whole, just as money reaches the point of no return when it is nothing more than a system of writing. Basically, political economy is only constructed (at the cost of untold sacrifices) or designed so as to be recognized as immortal by a future civilization, or as an instance of truth. As for religion, this is unimaginable other than in the Last Judgment, where God recognizes his own. But the Last Judgment is there already, realized: it is the definitive spectacle of our crystallized death. The spectacle is, it must be said, grandiose. From the hieroglyphic schemes of the Defense Department or the World Trade Center to the great informational schemes of the media, from siderurgical complexes to grand political apparatuses, from the megapolises with their senseless control of the slightest and most everyday acts: humanity, as Benjamin says, has everywhere become an object of contemplation to itself. Its self-alienation has reached such a degree that it can experience its own destruction as an aesthetic pleasure of the first order. (‘The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction’, in Illuminations tr. Harry Zohn, ed. Hannah Arendt, London: Jonathan Cape: 1970, p. 244) For Benjamin, this was the very form of fascism, that is to say, a certain exacerbated form of ideology, an aesthetic perversion of politics, pushing the acceptance of a culture of death to the point of jubilation. And it is true that today the whole system of political economy has become the finality without end and the aesthetic vertigo of productivity to us, and this is only the contrasting vertigo of death. This is exactly why art is dead: at the point of saturation and sophistication, all this jubilation has passed into the spectacle of complexity itself, and all aesthetic fascination has been monopolized by the system as it grows into its own double (what else would it do with its gigantic towers, its satellites, its giant computers, if not double itself as signs?). We are all victims of production become spectacle, of the aesthetic enjoyment jouisseance, of delirious production and reproduction, and we are not about to turn our backs on it, for in every spectacle there is the immanence of the catastrophe. Today, we have made the vertigo of politics that Benjamin denounces in fascism, its perverse aesthetic enjoyment, into the experience of production at the level of the general system. We produce the experience of a de-politicised, de-ideologised vertigo of the rational administration of things, of endlessly exploding finalities. B is Body Counts. Death debating reduces peoples’ lives to mere numbers for debaters to consume in their game. Baudrillard 93 More importantly, that everyone should have a right to their life (habeas corpus – habeas vitam) extends social jurisdiction over death. Death is socialized like everything else, and can no longer be anything but natural, since every other death is a social scandal: we have not done what is necessary. Is this social progress? No, it is rather the progress of the social, which even annexes death to itself. Everyone is dispossessed of their death, and will no longer be able to die as it is now understood. One will no longer be free to live as long as possible. Amongst other things, this signifies the ban on consuming one’s life without taking limits into account. In short, the principle of natural death is equivalent to the neutralization of life. 28 The same goes for the question of equality in death: life must be reduced to quantity (and death therefore to nothing) in order to adjust it to democracy and the law of equivalences. The same objective that is inscribed in the monopoly of institutional violence is accomplished as easily by forced survival as it is by death: a forced ‘life for life’s sake’ (kidney machines, malformed children on life-support machines, agony prolonged at all costs, organ transplants, etc.). All these procedures are equivalent to disposing of death and imposing life, but according to what ends? Those of science and medicine? Surely this is just scientific paranoia, unrelated to any human objective. Is profit the aim? No: society swallows huge amounts of profit This 'therapeutic heroism is characterised by soaring costs and 'decreasing benefits': they manufacture unproductive survivors_ Even if social security can still be analysed as 'compensation for the labour force in the interests of capital, this argument has no purchase here_ Nevertheless: the system is facing the same contradiction here as with the death penalty. it overspends on the prolongation of life because this system of values is essential to the strategic equilibrium of the whole; economically: however, this overspending unbalances the whole_ What is to be done? An economic choice becomes necessary, where we can see the outline of euthanasia as a semi-official doctrine or practice_ We choose to keep 30 per cent of the uraemics in France alive (36 per cent in the USA!). Euthanasia is already everywhere, and the ambiguity of making a humanist demand for it (as with the 'freedom' to abortion) is striking: it is inscribed in the middle to long term logic of the system. All this tends in the direction of an increase in social control. For there is a clear objective behind all these apparent contradictions: to ensure control over the entire range of life and death. From birth control to death control, whether we execute people or compel their survival (the prohibition of dying is the caricature, but also the logical form of progressive tolerance), the essential thing is that the decision is withdrawn from them: that their life and their death are never freely theirs, but that they live or die according to a social visa. It is even intolerable that their life and death remain open to biological chance, since this is still a type of freedom. Just as morality commanded you shall not kill', today it commands: 'You shall not die', not in any old way. anyhow, and only if the law and medicine permit. And if your death is conceded you, it will still be by order. In short: death proper has been abolished to make room for death control and euthanasia strictly speaking, it is no longer even death, but something completely neutralised that comes to be inscribed in the rules and calculations of equivalence: rewriting-planning-programming-system. It must be possible to operate death as a social service, integrate it like health and disease under the sign of the Plan and Social Security. This is the store of 'motel-suicides' in the USA, where, for a comfortable sum, one can purchase one's death under the most agreeable conditions (like any other consumer good); perfect service, everything has been foreseen, even trainers who give you back your appetite for life, after which they kindly and conscientiously send the gas into your room, without torment and without meeting any apposition. A service operates these motel-suicides, quite rightly paid (eventually reimbursed?). Why did death not become a social service when: like everything else: it is functionalised as individual and computable consumption in social input and output? Their use of death imagery is meant to sustain an irrational fear—Death is a fantasy. Biology means we cannot truly “die” or cease to be, rather we enter a new form of becoming: becoming earth. Becoming decomposition. Even if we are all wiped from the face of the earth in a hailstorm of nuclear bombs the process of life goes on even at the micro level. There is no unique warrant for why the biological construct of human deserves a place higher than the construct of atoms. This desire to be secure from death is the most personal level of microfascism that negates our ability to live life to its fullest and breeds resentment. That means the K comes before theory – hatred of life and obsession with death far outweighs the rules of a high school debate round. Its not about what you find fair anymore, now its about your obsession with mortality. Deleuze and Guattari 72 But it seems that things are becoming very obscure, for what is this distinction between the experience of death and the model of death? Here again, is it a death desire? A being-far-death? Or rather an investment of death, even if speculative? None of the above. The experience of death is the most common of occurrences in the unconscious, precisely because it occurs in life and for life, in every passage or becoming, in every intensity as passage or becoming. It is in the very nature of every intensity to invest within itself the zero intensity starting from which it is produced, in one moment, as that which grows or diminishes according to an infinity of degrees (as Klossowski noted, "an afflux is necessary merely to signify the absence of intensity"). We have attempted to show in this respect how the relations of attraction and repulsion produced such states, sensations, and emotions, which imply a new energetic conversion and form the third kind of synthesis, the synthesis of conjunction. One might say that the unconscious as a real subject has scattered an apparent residual and nomadic subject around the entire compass of its cycle, a subject that passes by way of all the becomings corresponding to the included disjunctions: the last part of the desiring-machine, the adjacent part. These intense becomings and feelings, these intensive emotions, feed deliriums and hallucinations. But in themselves, these intensive emotions are closest to the matter whose zero degree they invest in itself. They control the unconscious experience of death, insofar as death is what is felt in every feeling, what never ceases and never finishes happening in every becoming-in the becoming-another-sex, the becoming-god, the becoming-a-race, etc., forming zones of intensity on the body without organs. Every intensity controls within its own life the experience of death, and envelops it. And it is doubtless the case that every intensity is extinguished at the end, that every becoming itself becomes a becoming-death! Death, then, does actually happen. Maurice Blanchot distinguishes this twofold nature dearly, these two irreducible aspects of death; the one, according to which the apparent subject never ceases to live and travel as a One·-"one never stops and never has done with dying"; and the other, according to which this same subject, fixed as I, actually dies-which is to say it finally ceases to die since it ends up dying, in the reality of a last instant that fixes it in this way as an I, all the while undoing the intensity, carrying it back to the zero that envelops it. From one aspect to the other, there is not at all a personal deepening, but something quite different: there is a return from the experience of death to the model of death, in the cycle of the desiring-machines. The cycle is closed. For a new departure, since this I is another? The experience of death must have given us exactly enough broadened experience, in order to live and know that the desiring-machines do not die. And that the subject as an adjacent part is always a "one" who conducts the experience, not an I who receives the model. For the model itself is not the I either, but the body without organs. And I does not rejoin the model without the model starting out again in the direction of another experience. Always going from the model to the experience, and starting out again, returning from the model to the experience, is what schizophrenizing death amounts to, the exercise of the desiring-machines (which is their very secret, well understood by the terrifying authors). The machines tell us this, and make us live it, feel it, deeper than delirium and further than hallucination: yes, the return to repulsion will condition other attractions, other functionings, the setting in motion of other working parts on the body without organs, the putting to work of other adjacent parts on the periphery that have as much a right to say One as we ourselves do. "Let him die in his leaping through unheard-of and unnamable things: other horrible workers will come; they will begin on the horizons where the other collapsed !"29 The Eternal Return as experience, and as the deterritorialized circuit of all the cycles of desire. How odd the psychoanalytic venture is. Psychoanalysis ought to be a song of life, or else be worth nothing at all. It ought, practically, to teach us to sing life. And see how the most defeated, sad .song of death emanates from it: eiapopeia. From the start, and because of his stubborn dualism of the drives, Freud never stopped trying to limit the discovery of a subjective or vital essence of desire as libido. But when the dualism passed into a death instinct against Eros, this was no longer a simple limitation, it was a liquidation of the libido. Reich did not go wrong here, and was perhaps the only one to maintain that the product of analysis should be a free and joyous person, a carrier of the life flows, capable of carrying them all the way into the desert and decoding them-even if this idea necessarily took on the appearance of a crazy idea, given what had become of analysis. He demonstrated that Freud, no less than lung and Adler, had repudiated the sexual position: the fixing of the death instinct in fact deprives sexuality of its generative role on at least one essential point, which is the genesis of anxiety, since this genesis becomes the autonomous cause of sexual repression instead of its result; it follows that sexuality as desire no longer animates a social critique of civilization, but that civilization on the contrary finds itself sanctified as the sale agency capable of opposing the death desire. And how. does. it do this? By in principle turning death against death, by making this turned-back death (la mort ret aurneev into a force of desire by putting it in the service of a pseudo life through an entire culture of guilt feeling. There is no need to tell all over how psychoanalysis culminates in a theory of culture that takes up again the age-old task of the ascetic ideal Nirvana, the cultural extract, judging life, belittling life, measuring life against death, and only retaining from life what the death of death wants very much to leave us with - a sublime resignation. As Reich says, when psychoanalysis began to speak of Eros, the whole world breathed a sigh of relief': one knew what this meant, and that everything was going to unfold within a mortified life, since Thanatos was now the partner of Eros, for worse but also for better. Psychoanalysis becomes the training ground of a new kind of priest, the director of bad conscience: bad conscience has made us sick, but that is what will cure us! Freud did not hide what was really at issue with the introduction of the death instinct: it is not a question of any fact whatever, but merely of a principle, a question of principle. The death instinct is pure silence, pure transcendence, not givable and not given in experience. This very point IS remarkable: It IS because death, according to Freud, has neither a model nor an experience, that he makes of it a transcendent principle."! So that the psychoanalysts who refused the death instinct did so for the same reasons as those who accepted it: some said that there was no death instinct since there was no model or experience in the unconscious; others, that there was a death instinct precisely because there was no model or experience. We say, to the contrary, that there is no death instinct because there is both the model and the experience of death in the unconscious. Death then is a part of the desiring-machine, a part that must itself be judged, evaluated in the functioning of the machine and the system of its energetic conversions, and not as an abstract principle. If Freud needs death as a principle, this is by virtue of the requirements of the dualism that maintains a qualitative opposition between the drives (you will not escape the conflict): once the dualism of the sexual drives and the ego drives has only a topological scope, the qualitative or dynamic dualism passes between Eros and Thanatos. But the same enterprise is continued and reinforced-eliminating the machinic element of desire, the desiring-machines. It is a matter of eliminating the libido, insofar as it implies the possibility of energetic conversions in the machine (Libido-Nurnen-Voluptas). It is a matter of imposing the idea of an energetic duality rendering the machinic transformations impossible, with everything obliged to pass by way of an indifferent neutral energy, that energy emanating from Oedipus and capable of being added to either of the two irreducible forms neutralizing, mortifying life.* The purpose of the topological and dynamic dualities is to thrust aside the point of view of functional multiplicity that alone is economic. (Szondi situates the problem clearly: why two kinds of drives qualified as molar, functioning mysteriously, which is to say Oedipally, rather than n genes of drives-eight molecular genes, for example-functioning machinically") If one looks in this direction for the ultimate reason why Freud erects a transcendent death instinct as a principle, the reason will be found in Freud's practice itself. For if the principle has nothing to do with the facts, it has a lot to do with the psychoanalyst's conception of psychoanalytic practice, a conception the psychoanalyst wishes to impose. Freud made the most profound discovery of the abstract subjective essence of desire-Libido. But since he re-alienated this essence, reinvesting it in a subjective system of representation of the ego, and since he receded this essence on the residual territoriality of Oedipus and under the despotic signifier of castration, he could no longer conceive the essence of life except in a form turned back against itself, in the form of death itself. And this neutralization, this turning against life, is also the last way in which a depressive and exhausted libido can go on surviving, and dream that it is surviving: "The ascetic ideal is an artifice for the preservation of life ... even when he wounds himself, this master of destruction, of self-destructing-the very wound itself compels him to live. . . ."32 It is Oedipus, the marshy earth, that gives off a powerful odor of decay and death; and it is castration, the pious ascetic wound, the signifier, that makes of this death a conservatory for the Oedipal life I advocate that we embrace the violence of the 1AC to affirm life. We need to break the cycle of resentment and overcome a crumbling world. Only through this can we achieve greatness. Faulkner 8 Most significantly, for the purposes of this essay, we can perhaps see now how for Nietzsche agency is compatible with innocence. Indeed, innocence— regarded as what is unsullied by moral thinking—is integral to the skillful exercise of agency. Understood in these terms, innocence is neither a precious ideal to be protected from the forces of chance nor a moralistic instrument for the meting of punishment to those who threaten society. Rather, innocence is conceived as a style of existence that becomes active by claiming to itself what chance throws up before it. Innocence would here suggest a resistance to passivity and victimhood and a choice to take part in the inevitability of the moment—even if this agency ultimately extinguishes the subject through which it is performed. Perhaps at this point, then, we might attempt a return to the acts of the 9/11 jumpers, who in the light of the above can be understood as agents of their own demise but in a manner that nonetheless does not compromise their innocence. The visions of falling bodies from the Twin Towers do not sit well with orthodox imagery surrounding 9/11 because they invoke an uncomfortable ambiguity with respect to their victim status. In their final moments of animation and on the precipice of death, these bodies occupy a middle space between life and death that renders us uncomfortable in our own mortality. But they also mark a cleavage between innocence and guilt: their decision to seize the opportunity to escape confinement within their smoky “tombs” signals a confusing complicity with the terrorists who had perpetrated the attacks. In the terms that Nietzsche (and Spinoza) set out above, the jumpers took an active part in the causes that led to their deaths—causes that originate in a terrorist plot against America. And in the eyes of some, this exposed them as irresolute, and even disloyal, in the face of what later emerged to be a monumental national threat. In theological terms also—and keeping in mind the religious frame through which many in the United States view global politics—Drew’s photograph, especially, resonates with a near-godly defiance of death: the subject’s fall can be read as the taking of a liberty against God, who claims a privilege with respect to determining who lives or dies. The image may thus evoke to the viewing public humanity’s primal scene and the original sin that it demonstrates: the taking of the fruit of knowledge that marks a new beginning for humanity. Even the photograph’s title would seem to suggest a proximity to the guilt through which humanity is engendered, by means of its irreparable separation from innocence. Likewise, its subject is separated from the other victims of the attacks who (more appropriately) awaited divine sanction on their lives and have thus continued to be redeemed (drawn back into the community’s fold) by means of the various ceremonies and purification rites since performed at Ground Zero. The resigned posture of the subject of “The Falling Man” surely gives the viewer pause: it looks like a suicide attempt, and the suicide cannot be connected to a redemptive innocence. Yet, according to Nietzsche’s refiguring of agency, the decision to die can be reconciled with innocence: and moreover, innocence comes to be the very condition of an agency—as opposed to (fictitious) free will—an agency that, rather, refuses the moralizing economy of guilt and punishment. The decision to jump hundreds of meters to one’s death from a burning building might seem a limited, and somewhat undesirable, instance of agency. Clearly, it is a choice these people would not have made on any other morning and in any other circumstance. In the light of Nietzsche’s account of agency as conditioned by context and circumstance, however, it is possible to count the jumpers among the innocents lost to 9/11—and to do so in full recognition of their specific choice to take their lives into their own hands. In the context of Nietzsche’s innocence of becoming, we may understand innocence as a suspension of moral judgment rather than as prior to (and separate from) social existence. Nietzschean innocence emerges from within existence and gives rise to an agency that responds to the chance necessities life occasions. Likewise, the innocence of becoming is not grounded in opposition to guilt but, rather, undercuts the understanding of social relations in terms of guilt and debt. For this reason, Nietzsche’s innocence of becoming furnishes the jumpers’ decision with a sense that would be otherwise unavailable, at least within the narrow parameters according to which moral action and worth are conventionally adjudged. In the absence of an acknowledgment of the jumpers’ choice (and of the possibility of making a decision to die in one’s own way, where the choice to live is unavailable), we will continue to misunderstand their relationship to these events and thus to limit their political agency. In the context of the 9/11 attacks, the innocent—understood through the vista of Judeo-Christian moral tradition—has become an eternally aggrieved icon of national identity: a perennially threatened and victimized creature of ressentiment who “in order to exist first needs a hostile external world” ( GM I:10). 32 Although it is important to acknowledge the suffering of those affected, and this may indeed include the nation as a whole, what Nietzsche’s innocence of becoming reveals is that the relationship to one’s suffering is far from straightforward. If we subscribe too readily to the status of innocent-to-be-protected—thus recoiling from suffering and requiring that the debts of enemies be paid in full—then we also deny the possibility of freedom opened by the affirmation of becoming. And such a predicament is all too well reflected in the erosion of civil liberties that is ongoing since the end of 2001 in the United States and elsewhere. But were we to allow ourselves to imagine being trapped within those buildings and to contemplate the possibility that one might still make a choice, perhaps identification with the falling man might open the citizen to a new kind of agency in relation to government and nationhood. Remembering that the imagination furnishes us with knowledge of our situation—by means of the traces of interactions impressed upon memory—then we are able to develop a capacity for agency by using our imaginations to understand the decisions of those who have lived through what we have not. Through the rubric offered by the jumper’s predicament, we might then imagine a mode of resistance against attack, wherein strength is reappropriated from the enemy—even in death. Our reinterpretation of the falling man as innocent thus allows for a conception of freedom with respect to the chance events that constrain action. But moreover, it also allows us to develop a resistance to governments’ attempts to render us passive subjects by means of the moral mantle of innocence by which we are both idealized and contained. Such a modest and situated exercise of agency would involve attentiveness to the diffuse and unexpected opportunities that arise in one’s locality, to actively participate in the causes of change. For instance, one could organize a demonstration, write letters to political representatives and newspapers, meet with others who share one’s values, walk to work, or recycle. Each of these activities, however humble or ambitious, contributes to the determination of life and prevents one being the mere passive object of external causes—disempowered and separated from agency. Such attunement to one’s situation, however, requires above all engaging one’s imagination: the site of ethical understanding—of what empowers the body and what the body should avoid. In this vein, we might reimagine the falling man as a figure of the active resistance that Nietzsche’s innocence of becoming teaches. And we can understand his final act of agency as such, without casting him out of the sanctum of human virtue. With respect to this reinterpretation of innocence, as a sensitivity to the specific opportunities that life grants, I will leave the last word to one who, mourning the loss of his wife, finds it within himself to understand her final decision: “Whether she jumped, I don’t know. I hoped that she had succumbed to the smoke but it doesn’t seem likely. In some ways it might just be the last element of control, that everything around you is happening and you can’t stop it, but this is something you can do. Jean Baudrillard, ‘93 (Symbolic Exchange and Death trans Iain Grant, p. 185-7) | 2/18/14 |
Determinism NCTournament: CPS | Round: 1 | Opponent: X | Judge: X If determinism is true, moral claims can't exist. First, the universe is causally closed which rules out free will. Papineau: David Papineau, “Naturalism,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2007. In the middle ... those physical antecedents. Second, either actions are pre-determined or they’re pure chance chance. Ayer: Ayer, A.J. “Freedom and Necessity.” In Free Will, ed. Watson, 1982. But now we ... back to determinism. Third, Bohmian QM prescribes an additional equation to determine all particle movements, rendering everything predetermined. This theory is 100 verifiable. Hoefer: Carl Hoefer ICREA Research Professor, Barcelona, SEP entry on causal determinism, 2010. In 1952 David ... and references therein. Fourth, its contradictory to say that an agent ought to do something they’re not in control of so the only ought that rational deliberation could allow is what happens. Streumer : Streumer, Bart. Reasons and Impossibility, 2004 The argument from ... having such results.36 Analytic contention | 1/3/14 |
Direct Payments CPTournament: Direct Payments CP | Round: 1 | Opponent: x | Judge: x Its competitive -- I extract resources C. Solvency: Even small cash transfers are ridiculously good at reducing poverty. Moss 2: The resource curse is not inevitable and resources can be enormously beneficial if managed properly. Greenstein Moss 11 Todd Moss, senior fellow at Center for Global Development. "Oil to Cash: Fighting the Resource Curse through Cash Transfers." Center for Global Development Working Paper 237. January 2011. JY | 2/19/14 |
Disclosure TheoryTournament: UPS | Round: 1 | Opponent: X | Judge: X A is the interpretation: Debaters must disclose their affirmative cases and plan texts with the first and last three words of each card and taglines, on the NDCA LD wiki at hsld.debatecoaches.org or put contact information on the wiki so debaters can contact them during the tournament to obtain citations for those positions. The disclosure must occur at least 30 minutes before the round. | 1/9/14 |
EITI CPTournament: berk | Round: 1 | Opponent: x | Judge: x It competes The EITI brings transparency to resource extraction and solves the aff. Kelley Kelley, Jeremy. "China in Africa: Curing the Resource Curse with Infrastructure and Modernization." Sustainable Development Law and Policy 12, no. 3 (2012): 35-41, 57-60. | 2/18/14 |
Enforcement Spec TTournament: x | Round: 1 | Opponent: x | Judge: x The emergence of implementation as a subject for policy analysis coincides closely with the discovery by policy analysts that decisions are not self- executing. Analysis of policy choices matters very little if the mechanism for implementing those choices is poorly understood. In answering the question, "What percentage of the work of achieving a desired governmental action is done when the preferred analytic alternative has been identified?" Allison estimated that, in the normal case, it was about 10 percent, leaving the remaining 90 percent in the realm of implementation Additionally its key to environmental policies since actors have to pay for when they violate environmental legislation. Marshall Environmental policies may be are implemented by schemes designed either to reduce pollution from current levels by directly regulating the amount discharged, or to shift the cost of pollution from society to the polluter himself by requiring him to pay for the environmental damage that he causes. The most desirable systems will tend to accomplish both goals. B. Violation
Elmore 80?Richard F. Elmore (prof. of political science at UWashington) Political Science Quarterly; 1980; p. 605 Boston College Environmental Affairs Law Review Volume 4 | Issue 2 Article 6 1-1-1975 Environmental Protection and the Role of the Civil Money Penalty: Some Practical and Legal Considerations David W. Marshall | 2/18/14 |
Function NCTournament: anything jan feb | Round: 1 | Opponent: x | Judge: x In some ways, moral disagreement seems to parallels the diversity of opinion as color to which shade of green is unique green. Unique green is that shade of green that is neither bluish nor yellowish. When asked to select the a particular shade shade which is unique green, different subjects with normal color vision will select different shades. As in the case of our controversial moral views, opinion about which shade is unique green not only fails to be unanimous, but is substantially divided. Perhaps if there were relatively widespread agreement as to which shade is unique green, then the dissenting judgments of a few who possessed otherwise normal color vision could be dismissed. But the fact that the actual division of opinion is substantial suggests that human beings are not reliable detectors of the relevant property. That relevantly similar creatures—since creatures with the same type of visual system—arrive at different verdicts when similarly situated seems to show that that kind of creature is simply not well equipped to detect the presence or absence of the property in question. That human beings are not, as a species, reliable detectors of unique green seems to tell against crediting any individual with knowledge that a certain shade is unique green, particularly if the individual knows of this general lack of reliability and has no good reason to think that he is exceptional in this respect. Note that although questions about which shade of green is unique green are hard questions for human beings, such questions do not present themselves to us as difficult ones. In fact, most subjects are quite confident of their initial judgments; each person’s view strikes her as obviously correct. This seems That’s parallel to the morality case: in the moral case too, many find that their own views about controversial moral questions strike them as obviously correct. The only way to derive an objective “ought” is to consider the agent’s function. Macintyre .A.N. Prior’s counter-example to this illustrates its breakdown adequately; from the premise ‘He is a sea captain’; the conclusion may be validly inferred that ‘He ought to do whatever a sea-captain ought to do’. This counter-example not only shows that there is no general principle of the type alleged; but it itself shows what is at least a grammatical truth—an ‘is’ premise can on occasion entail an ‘ought’ conclusion. From such factual premises as ‘This watch is grossly inaccurate and irregular in time-keeping’ and ‘This watch is too heavy to carry about comfortably’, the evaluative conclusion validly follows that ‘This is a bad watch’. From such factual premises as ‘He gets a better yield for this crop per acre than any farmer in the district’, ‘He has the most effective programme of soil renewal yet known’ and ‘His dairy herd wins all the first prizes at the agricultural shows’, the evaluative conclusion validly follows that ‘He is a good farmer’. Both of these arguments are valid because of the special character of the concepts of a watch and of a farmer. Such concepts are functional concepts; that is to say, we define both ‘watch’ and ‘farmer’ in terms of purpose of function which a watch or a farmer are characteristically expected to serve. It follows that the concept of a watch cannot be defined independently of the concept of a good watch nor the concept of a farmer independently of that of a good farmer; and that the criterion of something’s being a watch and the criterion of something’s being a good watch. Thus, the standard is consistency with the function of developing countries Util impacts don't link -- Extinction might be bad, but developing countries are solely concerned with developing and are not responsible for other concerns. Prefer the standard since
I contend that resource extraction is most consistent with a developing country’s function. Walter 13 The discussion above of the factors underlying environmental policy raises a number of points with respect to the developing countries. First, it is reasonable to infer that the demand for environmental quality is income-sensitive. As real income per capita rises, so does the propensity to allocate scarce resources to reducing environmental damage (4). If this is correct, it implies that high-income countries will tend to have more rigorous environmental standards than poor countries. The latter, it is argued, have a variety of social priorities that take precedence-housing, transportation and communication facilities, health and nutrition, employment and industrialization, etc. Pollution control uses up productive resources which could be applied to greater social advantage in one or more of these areas. Having attained advanced levels of performance in each of these areas, in contrast, the industrialized countries are in a much better position to support a major commitment to pollution control, and its social benefits are valued relatively more highly. Such differences in social priorities have been noted periodically by developing country spokesmen over the past decade. For example, the 1972United Nations Conference on the Human Environment heard a number of calls from developing countries like Brazil for the "privilege" of reaching pollution levels existing in the advanced countries, under the presumption that this would carry with it equally advanced levels of industrial development(5). The definition of "environment “that has been adopted by the United Nations Environmental Program(UNEP) reflects these same views. It is not limited to visual despoliation and environmental damage caused by air and water pollution and solid wastes, as it tends to be in the industrial countries. Rather, it is a much broader view which encompasses urban health and sanitation levels, housing, and similar elements which come much closer to the social priorities in developing countries. Again, it reflects the lower relative weight accorded conventional environmental problems by industrial-country definitions (6). Many developing countries feel they have little need to repair past environmental damage, concentrating instead on less drastic and expensive ways of preventing future damage. It is also argued that production in developing countries tends to be far less pollution-intensive-both for final products and for raw materials and intermediates- in part due to a greater degree of labor intensity. Another argument is that pollution control represents an inherently capital-intensive activity. Hence, strict environmental policies in the developing countries would absorb great amounts of precisely that factor of production in most scarce supply, and its costs would therefore be much higher, in relative terms, than in developed countries where capitalist relatively abundant and cheap. Sarah McGrath, Moral Disagreement and Moral Expertise, | 2/18/14 |
Gift KTournament: stanford and berkeley | Round: 1 | Opponent: x | Judge: x The Aff’s attempts at equality and justice gives indigenous populations the gift of inclusion and equality via environmental protection but this is really just a clever attempt at continuing discrimination and perpetuating power structures via narcissistic hegemony. Arrigo 1 The impediments to establishing democratic justice in contemporary American society have caused a national paralysis; one that has recklessly spawned an aporetic1 existence for minorities. The entrenched ideological complexities afflicting under- and nonrepresented groups (e.g., poverty, unemployment, illiteracy, crime) at the hands of political, legal, cultural, and economic power elites have produced counterfeit, perhaps even fraudulent, efforts at reform: Discrimination and inequality in opportunity prevail (e.g., Lynch and Patterson, 1996). The misguided and futile initiatives of the state, in pursuit of transcending this public affairs crisis, have fostered a reification, that is, a reinforcement of divisiveness. This time, however, minority groups compete with one another for recognition, affirmation, and identity in the national collective psyche (Rosenfeld, 1993). What ensues by way of state effort, though, is a contemporaneous sense of equality for all and a near imperceptible endorsement of inequality; a silent conviction that the majority still retains power. The “gift” of equality, procured through state legislative enactments as an emblem of democratic justice, embodies true (legitimated) power that remains nervously secure in the hands of the majority. The ostensible empowerment of minority groups is a facade; it is the ruse of the majority gift. What exists, in fact, is a simulacrum (Baudrillard, 1981, 1983) of equality (and by extension, democratic justice): a pseudo-sign image (a hypertext or simulation) of real sociopolitical progress. For the future relationship between equality and the social to more fully embrace minority sensibilities, calculated legal reform efforts in the name of equality must be displaced and the rule and authority of the status quo must be decentered. Imaginable, calculable equality is self-limiting and self-referential. Ultimately, it is always (at least) one step removed from true equality and, therefore, true justice. The ruse of the majority gift currently operates under the assumption of a presumed empowerment, which it confers on minority populations. Yet, the presented power is itself circumscribed by the stifling horizons of majority rule with their effects. Thus, the gift can only be construed as falsely eudemonic: An avaricious, although insatiable, pursuit of narcissistic legitimacy supporting majority directives. The commission (bestowal) of power to minority groups or citizens through prevailing state reformatory efforts underscores a polemic with implications for public affairs and civic life. We contend that the avenir (i.e., the “to come”) of equality as an (in)calculable, (un)recognizable destination in search of democratic justice is needed. However, we argue that this displacement of equality is unattainable if prevailing juridico-ethicopolitical conditions (and societal consciousness pertaining to them) remain fixed, stagnant, and immutable. In this article, we will demonstrate how the gift of the majority is problematic, producing, as it must, a narcissistic hegemony, that is, a sustained empowering of the privileged, a constant relegitimation of the powerful. Their horrifying accounts of the suffering indigenous populations undergo link explicitly. By trying to evoke a compassionate response the 1AC tries to get us to participate in its gift-giving regime in which he’s the benevolent carer. But The 1AC is not genuine caring. Rather its a fear and discomfort of feeling the oppressed’s conditions for ourselves. This reaffirms their narcissism. Arrigo 2 The tension Nietzsche creates around the topic of pity or, alternately, assistance and altruism, is felt strongly in Daybreak, Zarathustra, as well as in his Genealogy of Morals.27 Indeed, Nietzsche advances several important arguments that challenge the logic of altruism; that is, of giving in reaction to pity.28 The first and most frequently occurring of these objections to pity recognizes the psychic ascription of human weakness to the one who receives pity. “To offer pity,” writes Nietzsche, “is as good as to offer contempt . . . ”29 Offering pity, then, is an acknowledgment of the insufficiency or inadequacy of those who receive such “charitable” sentiments. The danger lies in the possibility that “the pupil whose nose is too often wiped will not wipe her own nose, the child whose parents’ love is too smothering will not become a mature adult . . . ”30 When we pity or intervene on behalf of others, a Nietzschean assessment would require that we consider whether there are unconscious restrictions on the quality of our assistance. Indeed, following Nietzsche’s position on pity, we might ask ourselves whether our altruistic endeavors are affected (motivated) by a reluctance to undermine the self-sufficiency of the recipient of our gift or not? Another tension that Nietzsche reveals concerning pity is more akin to that developed by Hobbes. In this argument, Nietzsche identifies the egoistic nature of pity and, in so doing, repudiates the possibility of altruistic pity. Nietzsche provides an ethical or moral objection to altruistic assistance, one premised on the recognition that no act is free from self-interest or self-concern. As he describes it: Let us reflect seriously upon this question: why do we leap after someone who has fallen into the water in front of us, even though we feel no kind of affection for him? Out of pity: at that moment we are thinking only of the other person – thus says thoughtlessness . . . The truth is: in the feeling of pity – I mean that which is usually and misleadingly called pity – we are, to be sure, not consciously thinking of ourselves but are doing so very strongly unconsciously . . . an accident which happens to another offends us: it would make us aware of our impotence . . . Or an accident and suffering incurred by another constitutes a signpost to some danger to us . . . (emphasis added)31 Nietzsche makes two important points here: (1) that an act engaged out of pity is motivated by our contemplation of similar danger to ourselves rather than from pure compassion; and (2) that this and other egoistic concerns motivate largely from the level of the unconscious or, at least, from beneath or beyond the motives we are capable of experiencing on a conscious level. When we observe such suffering, we are reminded of the fragility of the human condition. To “repel” this kind of pain – this realization – we compensate through an act of pity, which “may contain a subtle self-defence;”32 namely, an affirmation of our own well-being, of the strength of our own capacity in light of the person we assist. Nietzsche indicates that we avoid sights of human suffering unless, we can “present ourselves as the more powerful and as a helper . . . if we want to feel how fortunate we are in contrast.” Environmental protection is a lie that that only exacerbates the minority’s conditions. Lazarus For example, with regard to the benefits of environmental protection, the 1 natural environments that are selected for protection may be less accessible, or otherwise less important, to minorities. This may be the result of priorities expressly established by statute, or by agency regulations or enforcement agenda. 2 Inequities in the ultimate distribution of environmental protection benefits may also result, paradoxically, from environmental improvement itself. 3 A cleaner physical environment may increase property values to such an extent that members of a racial minority with fewer economic resources so minorities can no longer afford to live in that community.3° Indeed, the exclusionary impact of environmental protection can be more than just an incidental effect; it can be the raison d'etre, with environmental quality acting as a socially acceptable facade for attitudes that cannot be broadcast.31 Minorities may at the same time incur a share of the burdens of environmental protection that are disproportionate to those benefits that they receive. 4 Higher product and service prices may be regressive, as may some taxes depending on their form.32 Although whites are poorer in greater absolute numbers than nonwhites, the latter group is disproportionately poorer in terms of population percentages. 5 Minorities may also more likely be the victims of reduced or eliminated job opportunities. Similarly, they may be less likely to enjoy the economic, educational, or personal positions necessary to exploit the new job opportunities that environmental protection creates.3s Finally, 6 minorities may receive an unfair share of the environmental risks that are redistributed by environmental protection. 7 Elimination of the risks in one location may result in the creation or increase of risks in another location where the exposure to minorities is greater. That makes the 1AC’s defiant call for change a tranquilizer, ensuring that the indigenous will never rise against them, entrapping them in their cycle of supposed altruism. The giver dominates the receiver resulting in endless violence as the receiver tries to perpetually repay the giver. Arrigo 3 To ground these observations about gift sending and receiving, the analo¬gous example of a loan may be helpful. Let us suppose that we have $100.00 and that you have $1.00. If we were to give you some of our money (less than $49 so as not to produce pecuniary equality), we would be subtlely engaged in a number of things. First, following Derrida (1997), we would be showing off our power (money) by exploiting the fact that we have so much more money than you do that we can give some away and remain in good fiscal standing. Second, And we would be expecting something in return—maybe not immediately, but eventually. This return could take several forms. Although we may not expect financial reciprocation, it would be enough knowing that you know that we helped have given currency to you. Thus, you are now indebted to us and forever grateful, realizing our good deed: our gift. Reciprocation on your part is impossible. Even if one day you are able to return our monetary favor twofold, we will always know that it was us who we first hosted you; extended to and entrusted in you an opportunity given your time of need. As the initiators of such a charity, we are always in a position of power, and you are always indebted to us. This is where the notion of egoism or conceit assumes a hegemonic role. By giving to you, a supposed act of gen¬erosity in the name of furthering your cause, we have not empowered you. Rather, we have empowered ourselves. We have less than subtlely let you know that we have more than you. We have so much more, in fact, that we can afford to give you some. Our giving becomes, not an act of beneficence, but a show of power, that is, narcissistic hegemony. Arrigo, Bruce and Williams, Christopher (California School of Professional Psychology), 2000 “The (Im) Possibility of Democratic Justice and the "Gift" of the Majority.” Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice. Richard J. Lazarus “Pursuing "Environmental Justice": The Distributional Effects of Environmental Protection” Georgetown Law. | 2/18/14 |
Ice Age DATournament: ups | Round: 5 | Opponent: x | Judge: x The coming Ice Age outweighs any impacts. Singer Chapman, geophysicist and astronautical engineer, ‘8 (Phil, April 23th 2008, The Australian, “Sorry to ruin the fun, but an ice age cometh.” | 2/19/14 |
Implementation T -- Buen Vivir VersionTournament: ups | Round: 6 | Opponent: x | Judge: x These are social democratic policies that have nothing to do with environmental protection C is Predictable and Equitable Ground -- Allowing him to be extra topical means that he can moot all topical prep just by saying that he doesn't defend links to those disads. My interp is the only way to have any ground at all and then divide that ground equally since all ground in debate comes from the resolution which is the basis for all pre-round prep. That controls the internal link into education since since ground is the only way we ge tot make arguments and discuss issues and its key to fairness since equal ground creates equal access to the ballot. Catherine Walsh 10,Senior Professor and Director of the Doctoral Programme in Latin American Cultural Studies, Universidad Andina Simon Boliva, "Development as Buen Vivir: Institutional Arrangements and (de)colonial entanglements), Development, 2010, 53 (1). | 2/19/14 |
NGOs Bad TTournament: lol | Round: 1 | Opponent: no | Judge: clue
D. Jurisdiction | 2/18/14 |
NOTETournament: all of em | Round: 1 | Opponent: everyone | Judge: anyone Anyways, obviously I might forget something, so in case I do, let me know and I'll disclose whatever I forgot too. | 2/19/14 |
Neolib TTournament: berkeley | Round: 1 | Opponent: x | Judge: x B: Violation: they don't C: Net Benefits First is decision-making, a limited and specific discussion is key to making actual change in the debate space and fosters argumentative innovation. Steinberg (David L. and Austin J., Argumentation and Debate: Critical Thinking for Reasoned Decision Making p. 45) Debate is a means of settling differences, so there must be a difference of opinion or a conflict of interest before there can be a debate. If everyone is in agreement on a tact or value or policy, there is no need for debate: the matter can be settled by unanimous consent. Thus, for example, it would be pointless to attempt to debate "Resolved: That two plus two equals four," because there is simply no controversy about this statement. (Controversy is an essential prerequisite of debate. Where there is no clash of ideas, proposals, interests, or expressed positions on issues, there is no debate. In addition, debate cannot produce effective decisions without clear identification of a question or questions to be answered. For example, general argument may occur about the broad topic of illegal immigration. How many illegal immigrants are in the United States? What is the impact of illegal immigration and immigrants on our economy? What is their impact on our communities? Do they commit crimes? Do they take jobs from American workers? Do they pay taxes? Do they require social services? Is it a problem that some do not speak English? Is it the responsibility of employers to discourage illegal immigration by not hiring undocumented workers? Should they have the opportunity- to gain citizenship? Docs illegal immigration pose a security threat to our country? Do illegal immigrants do work that American workers are unwilling to do? Are their rights as workers and as human beings at risk due to their status? Are they abused by employers, law enforcement, housing, and businesses? I low are their families impacted by their status? What is the moral and philosophical obligation of a nation state to maintain its borders? Should we build a wall on the Mexican border, establish a national identification can!, or enforce existing laws against employers? Should we invite immigrants to become U.S. citizens? Surely you can think of many more concerns to be addressed by a conversation about the topic area of illegal immigration. Participation in this "debate" is likely to be emotional and intense. However, it is not likely to be productive or useful without focus on a particular question and identification of a line demarcating sides in the controversy. To be discussed and resolved effectively, controversies must be stated clearly. Vague understanding results in unfocused deliberation and poor decisions, frustration, and emotional distress, as evidenced by the failure of the United States Congress to make progress on the immigration debate during the summer of 2007. Someone disturbed by the problem of the growing underclass of poorly educated, socially disenfranchised youths might observe, "Public schools are doing a terrible job! They are overcrowded, and many teachers are poorly qualified in their subject areas. Even the best teachers can do little more than struggle to maintain order in their classrooms." That same concerned citizen, facing a complex range of issues, might arrive at an unhelpful decision, such as "We ought to do something about this" or. worse. "It's too complicated a problem to deal with." Groups of concerned citizens worried about the state of public education could join together to express their frustrations, anger, disillusionment, and emotions regarding the schools, but without a focus for their discussions, they could easily agree about the sorry state of education without finding points of clarity or potential solutions. A gripe session would follow. But if a precise question is posed—such as "What can be done to improve public education?"—then a more profitable area of discussion is opened up simply by placing a focus on the search for a concrete solution step. One or more judgments can be phrased in the form of debate propositions, motions for parliamentary debate, or bills for legislative assemblies. The statements "Resolved: That the federal government should implement a program of charter schools in at-risk communities" and "Resolved: That the state of Florida should adopt a school voucher program" more clearly identify specific ways of dealing with educational problems in a manageable form, suitable for debate. They provide specific policies to be investigated and aid discussants in identifying points of difference. To have a productive debate, which facilitates effective decision making by directing and placing limits on the decision to be made, the basis for argument should be clearly defined. If we merely talk about "homelessness" or "abortion" or "crime'* or "global warming" we are likely to have an interesting discussion but not to establish profitable basis for argument. For example, the statement "Resolved: That the pen is mightier than the sword" is debatable, yet fails to provide much basis for clear argumentation. If we take this statement to mean that the written word is more effective than physical force for some purposes, we can identify a problem area: the comparative effectiveness of writing or physical force for a specific purpose. Although we now have a general subject, we have not yet stated a problem. It is still too broad, too loosely worded to promote well-organized argument. What sort of writing are we concerned with—poems, novels, government documents, website development, advertising, or what? What does "effectiveness" mean in this context? What kind of physical force is being compared—fists, dueling swords, bazookas, nuclear weapons, or what? A more specific question might be. "Would a mutual defense treaty or a visit by our fleet be more effective in assuring Liurania of our support in a certain crisis?" The basis for argument could be phrased in a debate proposition such as "Resolved: That the United States should enter into a mutual defense treatv with Laurania." Negative advocates might oppose this proposition by arguing that fleet maneuvers would be a better solution. This is not to say that debates should completely avoid creative interpretation of the controversy by advocates, or that good debates cannot occur over competing interpretations of the controversy; in fact, these sorts of debates may be very engaging. The point is that debate is best facilitated by the guidance provided by focus on a particular point of difference, which will be outlined in the following discussion. That controls the internal link into education since it dictates what we learn about, which in turn is another internal link into their role of the ballot arguments. Limiting the discussion to a specific governmental policy means that we can explore it more in depth and have a productive discussion that will spill over into the real world and create REAL change. Second is dialogue – debate is communication within a game space – unbridled affirmation outside that space destroys dialogue Hanghoj Debate games are often based on pre-designed scenarios that include descriptions of issues to be debated, educational goals, game goals, roles, rules, time frames etc. In this way, debate games differ from textbooks and everyday classroom instruction as debate scenarios allow teachers and students to actively imagine, interact and communicate within a domain-specific game space. However, instead of mystifying debate games as a “magic circle” (Huizinga, 1950), I will try to overcome the epistemological dichotomy between “gaming” and “teaching” that tends to dominate discussions of educational games. In short, educational gaming is a form of teaching. As mentioned, education and games represent two different semiotic domains that both embody the three faces of knowledge: assertions, modes of representation and social forms of organisation (Gee, 2003; Barth, 2002; cf. chapter 2). In order to understand the interplay between these different domains and their interrelated knowledge forms, I will draw attention to a central assumption in Bakhtin’s dialogical philosophy. According to Bakhtin, all forms of communication and culture are subject to centripetal and centrifugal forces (Bakhtin, 1981). A centripetal force is the drives to impose one version of the truth, while a centrifugal force involves a range of possible truths and interpretations. This means that any form of expression involves a duality of centripetal and centrifugal forces: “Every concrete utterance of a speaking subject serves as a point where centrifugal as well as centripetal forces are brought to bear” (Bakhtin, 1981: 272). If we take teaching as an example, it is always affected by centripetal and centrifugal forces in the on-going negotiation of “truths” between teachers and students. In the words of Bakhtin: “Truth is not born nor is it to be found inside the head of an individual person, it is born between people collectively searching for truth, in the process of their dialogic interaction” (Bakhtin, 1984a: 110). Similarly, the dialogical space of debate games also embodies centrifugal and centripetal forces. Thus, the election scenario of The Power Game involves centripetal elements that are mainly determined by the rules and outcomes of the game, i.e. the election is based on a limited time frame and a fixed voting procedure. Similarly, the open-ended goals, roles and resources represent centrifugal elements and create virtually endless possibilities for researching, preparing, presenting, debating and evaluating a variety of key political issues. Consequently, the actual process of enacting a game scenario involves a complex negotiation between these centrifugal/centripetal forces that are inextricably linked with the teachers and students’ game activities. In this way, the enactment of The Power Game is a form of teaching that combines different pedagogical practices (i.e. group work, web quests, student presentations) and learning resources (i.e. websites, handouts, spoken language) within the interpretive frame of the election scenario. Obviously, tensions may arise if there is too much divergence between educational goals and game goals. This means that game facilitation requires a balance between focusing too narrowly on the rules or “facts” of a game (centripetal orientation) and a focusing too broadly on the contingent possibilities and interpretations of the game scenario (centrifugal orientation). For Bakhtin, the duality of centripetal/centrifugal forces often manifests itself as a dynamic between “monological” and “dialogical” forms of discourse. Bakhtin illustrates this point with the monological discourse of the Socrates/Plato dialogues in which the teacher never learns anything new from the students, despite Socrates’ ideological claims to the contrary (Bakhtin, 1984a). Thus, discourse becomes monologised when “someone who knows and possesses the truth instructs someone who is ignorant of it and in error”, where “a thought is either affirmed or repudiated” by the authority of the teacher (Bakhtin, 1984a: 81). In contrast to this, dialogical pedagogy fosters inclusive learning environments that are able to expand upon students’ existing knowledge and collaborative construction of “truths” (Dysthe, 1996). At this point, I should clarify that Bakhtin’s term “dialogic” is both a descriptive term (all utterances are per definition dialogic as they address other utterances as parts of a chain of communication) and a normative term as dialogue is an ideal to be worked for against the forces of “monologism” (Lillis, 2003: 197-8). In this project, I am mainly interested in describing the dialogical space of debate games. At the same time, I agree with Wegerif that “one of the goals of education, perhaps the most important goal, should be dialogue as an end in itself” (Wegerif, 2006: 61). Dialogue is critical to affirming any value—shutting down deliberation devolves into totalitarianism and reinscribes oppression making dialogue an independent voter Morson 4 Bakhtin viewed the whole process of “ideological” (in the sense of ideas and values, however unsystematic) development as an endless dialogue. As teachers, we find it difficult to avoid a voice of authority, however much we may think of ours as the rebel’s voice, because our rebelliousness against society at large speaks in the authoritative voice of our subculture.We speak the language and thoughts of academic educators, even when we imagine we are speaking in no jargon at all, and that jargon, inaudible to us, sounds with all the overtones of authority to our students. We are so prone to think of ourselves as fighting oppression that it takes some work to realize that we ourselves may be felt as oppressive and overbearing, and that our own voice may provoke the same reactions that we feel when we hear an authoritative voice with which we disagree. So it is often helpful to think back on the great authoritative oppressors and reconstruct their self- That controls the internal link into their role of the ballot arguments, since dialogue and deliberation must be constrained by the rules of the game to have any impact on the outside world. Otherwise we deceive ourselves into thinking that we stop oppression but in reality only perpetuate it. D is the impact Vote Neg to affirm the role of the ballot, they try to create an actual change but in doing so they turn themselves. | 2/18/14 |
Psychoanalysis KTournament: ups | Round: 8 | Opponent: x | Judge: x What constitutes the modern subject is hardly green pastures and eternal bliss but rather the endless drive to fulfill our final desires. This death drive is fed by the proliferation of the small quick fix promises like the plan. Signing a ballot doesn't get rid of our nightmares. PULP FICTION PROVES, YO. Daly The only way to deal with the political hijacking of environmental issues is to radically realign the symbolic coordinates within which we exist. Only by radically altering our symbolic coordinates can we break out of the post-political hold over liberal ideologies. Swyngedouw Joseph, MPhil, Psychoanalytic Studies, Sheffield University, UK, MA, Psychoanalytic Studies, Sheffield University, UK BSc, Psychology and Neuroscience, Manchester University, UK, Chartered Psychologist (CPsychol) of the British Psychological Society (BPS), and a member of several other professional organizations such as the International Neuropsychoanalysis Society, Psychoanalysis and Ecology at the Edge of Chaos p 27 *gender mod Daly, 2004, (Glyn, Risking the Impossible, http://www.lacan.com/zizek-primer.htm) SRM Swyngedouw, Dept of Geography, School of Environment and Development, Manchester University, 2006. Eirk, “Impossible “Sustainability” and the Post-Political Condition,” Forthcoming in: David Gibbs and Rob Krueger (Eds.) Sustainable Development, http://www.liv.ac.uk/geography/seminars/Sustainabilitypaper.doc | 2/19/14 |
Reincarnation CardTournament: CPS | Round: Doubles | Opponent: Srikar Pyda | Judge: Panel The subtitle of...created or destroyed. | 1/3/14 |
Sugarcane CPTournament: stanford | Round: 9 | Opponent: nobody i think | Judge: nobody i think Its mutually exclusive since it extracts resources. Solves oil dependence and warming. Matthews and Steglich, 11 Note that the USA produces about 11 and consumes about 25 of world demand. Recent increases are attributable largely to growing economies in China, India, and other developing countries. At the current rate of worldwide oil consumption, the above worldwide oil reserves equate to about 44 years of production. Of course, total proved reserves includes both developed and undeveloped reserves, and a substantial portion of the total proved reserves have yet to be developed and produced. Such development and production will require considerable expenditures. For economic reasons, therefore, we have tended generally to have somewhere in the range of 10-15 years of developed and producing reserves at any time. Of course, we cannot accurately determine the amount of reserves present until they are developed and produced, but these estimates are developed using reasonable methodologies. What must be understood is that this does not mean we have 10 or 15 or 44 years before the oil runs out. The “peak oil” question must be addressed when new discoveries start to run out, but that has not been the case yet. However, at some point the question of how long we can continue to rely on oil must be faced. Given that the 44 years of reserves identified above represent what has been found with technology to date, and that finding new reserves is becoming technologically more difficult and substantially more expensive, it is not unreasonable to infer from the above that the era of relatively cheap oil will be over within something approaching 50 years, and therefore we need to be migrating away from oil in earnest by that time. The problem with migrating away from oil is that it has proved to be very difficult to find a reasonable alternative to oil. Sandalow has identified ten key facts about oil, each with an important implication, as follows (Sandalow, 2008): One reason that oil is so hard to replace is that it is a relatively efficient energy source. Cleveland, Costanza, Hall, and Kaufmann compared the “energy profit ratio” of various renewable and nonrenewable energy sources (Cleveland, et al, 1984), and Howard T. Odum compared the “energy yield ratio” (Odum, 1976). Their findings were summarized by Richard Heinberg (Heinberg, 2006, pp 162-164). Oil has yield rates in the range of 8 to 11 and natural gas in the range of 7 to 10, with coal even higher. Among alternatives, only sugar cane ethanol (8.3 to 10.2, per Goettemoeller, 2007), 100-year growth rainforest (12.0 per Odum), hydroelectric (11.2 per Cleveland and 10.0 per Odum), solar photovoltaics (1.7 to 10.0, per Cleveland), geothermal from hot dry rock (1.9 to 13.0 per Cleveland and 13.0 per Odum), and tidal electric with a 25-foot tide range (15.0 per Odum). The fossil fuels (oil, natural gas, coal) as a group produce significantly higher energy profit ratios or energy yield ratios than do most green alternatives. This differential is typically reflected in price; we depend so heavily on oil, and to a lesser extent on other fossil fuels, because they provide more energy cheaper than do the currently available alternatives. One barrier to alternative energy sources is that the cost of those alternatives is higher than the cost of oil. However, the cost of oil is also rising. As time passes, we are still making significant discoveries (such as Brazil’s finds in the Campos, Santos, and Espirito Santo basins) and as prices rise so will oil supplies, as some known reservoirs are economically viable to produce only at higher prices. But we appear to have found most of the “easy” oil, and what is discovered in the future can reasonably be expected to be more expensive to produce. Green, Jones, and Leiby, in a 1995 report prepared for the Office of Transportation Technology of the United States Department of Energy, forecasted that “in the long run the net price of oil (price minus marginal extraction costs) will rise steadily at the rate of interest” (Green, et al, 1995, p. 5). Since that time, oil prices have fluctuated wildly but the overall trend is clearly upward. The Energy Information Administration of the U.S. Department of Energy (DOE/EIA) prepares an annual energy report and forecast with projections of future energy supply and demand, specifically projecting supply and demand components for 2020 and 2030. The 2007 and 2009 forecasts (DOE/EIA, 2007 and DOE/EIA, 2009) can be compared as follows (reference case, volumes in quadrillion Btu/year): The 2009 forecast differs from the 2007 forecast primarily in that it considers the impact of the decline in energy consumption during the latter half of 2008. Although both forecasts predict an increase in domestic oil and gas production as well as energy from other source, both forecasts leave the U.S. very much dependent on foreign oil as far into the future as 2030. President Barack Obama has stated, "And for the sake of our economy, our security, and the future of our planet, I will set a clear goal as president: In 10 years, we will finally end our dependence on oil from the Middle East (Obama, 8/28/2008).” Unfortunately, it does not appear that the energy program outline by President Obama will accomplish that goal. Efforts to develop wind, solar, and improved insulation for buildings will have minimal impacts on oil usage. Perhaps the signature element—the electric automobile—is now coming into use, with a goal of 1 million on the road by 2015 (Obama, 1/25/2011). Assuming that each electric vehicle saves 4 gallons of gasoline per day, achieving that goal would reduce current oil consumption by about 200,000 barrels per day, or less than 1 percent. It is entirely likely that on the current path, the US will import more oil in 2015 than today, thus continuing the trend of the last 40 years of becoming ever more dependent on foreign oil. To date, the US has fallen far short of its intended goal of reducing its dependency on foreign oil. In fact that dependency has increased rather than decreased. It is the opinion of the authors that this results from three flaws in the US approach: ? There has been a focus on developing a perfect solution in a laboratory environment and then implementing it, rather than making use of what is available. ? Particularly with respect to oil, the perfect alternative has not been found, nor at this point is there any strong suggestion of what it might be. ? Regulations have hampered many private sector efforts to develop solutions. As a result the US finds itself in a position where it must address two potentially negative factors: ? The era of cheap energy is coming to an end. ? We currently have no good substitutes for oil. THE APPROACH TAKEN BY BRAZIL Brazil, which was even more dependent on foreign oil than was the U.S. in the 1970s, is today virtually energy-independent. Because of transportation considerations and difficulties refining heavy oil, Brazil does import some oil, primarily from Bolivia (although that is expected to change once production in the offshore Campos, Santos, and Espirito Santo basins is up to speed), but it exports sufficient oil to be a net exporter of energy. Brazil is now among the ten largest suppliers of oil to the USA. Clearly, the Brazilian economy in general, and its energy consumption in particular, is significantly smaller than in the USA, so some lessons are not strictly applicable. However, Brazil clearly did some things better than the U.S., and there are some broad general principles that have significant applicability. Brazil’s well-known and massive effort to develop alternatives to gasoline (sugar cane ethanol) and diesel fuel (soybean-based biodiesel) has replaced approximately 50 of gasoline and 44 of the country’s on-the-road motor fuel. It should be noted that criticism that Brazil has destroyed the Amazon basin to produce ethanol is unfounded. Sugar cane is produced in the Brazilian states of Mato Grosso, Mato Grosso do Sul, Goias, Minas Gerais, Sao Paulo, Parana, Rio de Janeiro, Espirito Santo, Rio Grande do Norte, Paraiba, Pernambuco, Alagoas, and Sergipe. The area with maximum potential for expansion lies in the states of Mato Grosso, Mato Grosso do Sul, and Goias. All these areas lie outside the Amazon basin (Lachlau, Sergio Andre, in Schwind, 2007). Further, it is estimated that approximately 65 of the area now producing sugar cane was converted from pasture land before. Brazil does also produce a significant amount of biodiesel, primarily from soybeans, and a considerable amount of soybean production does take place in areas that have been cleared in the Amazon basin. What may be less well known is that Brazil’s approach also included significant amounts of increased domestic exploration for oil and gas (the source of the other 56 of motor fuel) and hydroelectric (35 of Brazil’s total energy needs). Today Petrobras is perhaps the world’s leading center of expertise in deep water drilling. This has resulted in significant new finds in the offshore Santos, Campos and Espirito Santo basins. While Brazil’s recoverable reserves of oil and gas are less than those of the U.S., they are growing rapidly, and continued development could transform Brazil into one of the largest oil producers in the world (DOE/EIA, Brazil country brief, 2011). This emphasis on a broad frontal attack on the problem from all sources was accompanied by a strong bias in favor of action, specifically action utilizing known technology rather than waiting for future technologies to prove themselves. The ethanol plants are themselves relatively primitive, particularly when compared to a U.S. oil refinery (Schwind, 2007). Brazil has refused to become slave to “perfect” or to allow “perfect” to become the worst enemy of “good enough.” This is quite a contrast to the U.S. effort, where there has been considerable research into a “perfect” solution, but comparatively little effort to get “good enough” solutions implemented. Brazil’s approach also included a heavy orientation toward the private sector and free markets. Realizing that as a government-owned entity, Petrobras would likely be too bureaucratic and not sufficiently nimble to respond as needed, the government sold a large stake in the company and passed management duties and privileges to the non-government shareholders. Brazil moved further toward a free-market approach by ending Petrobras’s exclusive concession to develop all domestic oil and gas, and invited foreign companies to come in and take down exploration and production concessions. The mechanisms whereby sugar growers determine whether to sell there produce for making into sugar or into ethanol, and similarly the mechanisms whereby motorists decide whether to burn gasoline or ethanol in their autos (which are set up to burn either) rely almost entirely upon free-market principles. The sugar cane grower compares the prices he can receive at the sugar mill and at the ethanol plant before deciding where to sell his crop. Because automobiles and trucks are configured to run on either gasoline/diesel or ethanol/bio-diesel, the motorist can check the price of each, adjust for performance differential, and make a rational economic decision which one she should put into her vehicle today. Using sugar cane ethanol as the “swing” product introduces some price elasticity to both sugar and oil. While the sugar market is depressed today, lower sugar prices mean that farmers will deliver more sugar cane to the ethanol plant, and ethanol prices give some insulation against oil—and resulting gasoline—price shocks. The lessons to be learned from the Brazilian experience may be summarized as follows: Table 8 United States Of America Brazil The U.S. has debated the question of “drill here, drill now” versus alternatives versus conservation. The emphasis has been on debate and discussion rather than action. Brazil pursued all available options vigorously and simultaneously. The Brazilian approach has been “drill here, drill now” plus alternatives plus conservation. There has been a strong bias toward action. The U.S. has focused upon developing the “perfect” solution in the laboratory and then bringing that solution to reality. Brazil utilized existing technology to the maximum extent possible, and phased in improved technologies as they make the transition from laboratory to real world usefulness. Brazil has vigorously avoided letting “perfect” get in the way of “good enough”. The U.S. government has maintained an adversarial stance toward the energy industry, and has sought to regulate its activities heavily. Brazil has pushed toward a more cooperative approach with the energy industry, and generally allowed the free market to work. APPLYING THE LESSONS FROM BRAZIL TO THE UNITED STATES These lessons learned from Brazil can be applied to address the USA’s energy problems. Conservation, alternatives, and increased production from conventional domestic sources must be accompanied by vigorous research and development effort. Rather than wait for perfect technology to be developed, the timing is such that we need to implement some “good enough” steps today. Participation by the private sector in an energy market that sends the right price signals is the fastest way to make real progress; this requires a more cooperative, rather than adversarial, relationship with government, and efforts to ensure that free markets send the proper economic signals. The good news is that a solution appears possible. The bad news is that it will not be cheap. The era of cheap energy is over. Pursuing All Available Options Pursuing all available options means that conservation, alternative fuels, and increased production of domestic fuel—fossil and non-fossil—must be accomplished vigorously and simultaneously. Conservation The potential to “find” energy by saving it through conservation is enormous. The USA currently consumes 68.672 barrels of oil per day per 1,000 people, compared to Europe’s 29.42 barrels of oil per day per 1,000 people. Of particular note is that several European countries are able to maintain GDP per capita at, near, or above US levels, with significantly lower energy consumption: Admittedly, Europe has some advantages over the USA, which enable Europeans to use less energy: ? Europe is more compact, with less distance between population centers. ? Europe has generally better rail and public transit systems. ? European homes are generally much smaller, requiring less energy to heat and cool. ? Because Europe is so much further north, European summers are cooler, requiring less air conditioning, but this is offset somewhat because European winters are generally cooler, requiring more energy to heat. At the same time, these data suggest considerable potential for improvement. If the USA reduced its oil consumption to European levels, it would require no imports of oil from sources outside NAFTA. More realistically, a report prepared in 2005 for the Natural Resources Defense Council suggested that the United States could save an average of 2.5 million barrels per day by 2015 (Bordetsky, 2005). The proposed approach includes: ? Providing tax incentives to auto manufacturers to retool to build more energy-efficient vehicles ? Increasing the Corporate Adjusted Fuel Economy (CAFÉ) standards ? Requiring replacement tires and motor oil to be at least as fuel efficient as original equipment tires and motor oil; ? Requiring efficiency improvements in heavy-duty trucks; ? Supporting smart growth and better transportation choices. ? Expanding industrial efficiency programs to focus on oil use reduction and adopting standards for petroleum heating; ? Replacing chemical feedstocks with bioproducts through research and development and government procurement of bioproducts; Upgrading air traffic management systems so aircraft follow the most-efficient routes; and ? Promoting residential energy savings with a focus on oil-heat. Conservative commentator Charles Krauthammer has proposed a revenue-neutral consumption tax on gasoline to encourage conservation (Krauthammer, 2009). The principle behind this proposal is that a substantial tax be added to the price of motor fuel, with an offsetting reduction in the payroll tax. A driver who drove a lesser number of miles, or utilized a more fuel-efficient vehicle, than the standard would realize a net income from this approach. A variation of this approach is that revenue neutrality should apply to a majority of the tax, with the remainder comprising a net revenue stream that could be used to fund alternatives or research or infrastructure to reduce the use of oil. The savings resulting from the imposition of such a tax are not easily quantifiable, but reductions in consumption in response to the 2008 price spike would suggest that this could save at least 1 million barrels a day. Alternatives In the long run, the development of green energy technology will make the biggest difference in reducing or eliminating our dependence upon foreign, and even domestic, oil. The United States’ energy policy needs a more forceful approach to making alternative energy sources mainstream (Toal, 2008). Oil is a natural resource and will deplete in time and as the problem of global warming becomes more severe, the need for alternative fuel becomes more and more imperative (Luchansky and Monks, 2009). Unfortunately, in the short run all alternative fuels suffer from two basic shortcomings: ? Because the vast majority of oil is used for transportation, translating alternative energy into an alternative for oil is a difficult proposition. ? Alternatives compare poorly to traditional energy sources in at least one of the following areas: o Scale o Infrastructure o Price The relevant question, as stated by Richard Heinberg, ultimately becomes, “To what degree can any given non-petroleum energy source, or combination of sources enable industrial civilization to survive the end of oil?” (Heinberg, 2006, p.138) Heinberg further notes that the advantages of oil as an energy commodity, and by implication the disadvantages of alternatives, are that oil is: ? Easily transported (liquid fuels are more easily transported than solids such as coal or gases such as methane, and may be carried in ships far more easily than can be gases); ? Energy-dense (gasoline contains roughly 40 kilowatt-hours per gallon); ? Capable of being refined into several fuels (including gasoline, kerosene, and diesel fuel) suitable for a variety of applications; and ? Suitable for a variety of uses (including transportation, heating, and the production of chemicals and other materials) Because of the above limitations, the use of alternatives must be managed very carefully to obtain maximum advantage. As noted above, Brazil gets 50 of its “gasoline” and over 40 of its motor fuels from Biofuels. An equivalent ratio here would mean somewhere between 5 and 6 million barrels per day from Biofuels. That level is clearly achievable, with relatively inexpensive modifications to automobiles to enable flex fuel operations. The US currently gets about 1 million barrels a day from corn ethanol, and further growth expectations for that market are limited. The quickest possibility of a material impact probably lies with sugarcane ethanol from Latin America. Estimates are that as much as 10 of world gasoline usage could be replaced with sugar cane ethanol using current technology (Goldemberg, 2007). Ron Soligo has estimated the potential for sugar cane ethanol from Latin America to be 2.5 to 3 million barrels per day, depending on amount of land dedicated and yields obtained (Soligo and Jaffe, 2008). If the trade sanctions with Cuba were lifted, Juan Tomás Sanchez of the Association for the Study of the Cuban Economy estimates that Cuba alone could supply up to 3.2 billion gallons of ethanol annually (200,000 barrels/day, or 1 of total U.S. energy consumption), while Cuba expert Jorge Hernandez Fonseca projects a more modest production figure around 2 billion gallons per year (Elledge, 2009). The difficulty arises because the current sanctions make the acquisition of accurate information more difficult. Since Cuban sugar production has declined from 44 million tons/year in 1950 to 11 million tons/year today (Zuurbier, 2008), significant upside potential is obvious. These impacts are substantially larger than any other steps under consideration, except perhaps the “drill here, drill now” option. We would still be importing, but it would be from countries that are closer and have more in common than areas in the Middle East and elsewhere in the third world. The existence of a new cash crop in Latin America could dramatically improve their economies, reducing the pressure from illegal immigration, and could also provide farmers with an alternative to marijuana, cocaine, and other plants that are the source of many drugs currently being smuggled into the U.S. Moreover, the ability to use ethanol as a substitute for gasoline would introduce at least some elasticity into the gasoline consumption model, thereby limiting the exposure to oil price shocks in the future. The EPA estimates that use of sugar cane ethanol could reduce greenhouse gas (GHG) emissions by 61, compared to 21 for corn ethanol (EPA, 2011). Additional ethanol supplies could be obtained from domestic sugar cane and sugar beets. Estimating the potential production from these sources is difficult, but perhaps another 500,000 barrels per day would be possible. That would mean a total of 4 million barrels per day from ethanol, slightly less than the 40 number, but a significant reduction in oil consumption. Additionally, this would enable the installation of significant ethanol infrastructure now, to be in place already when more exotic forms of ethanol, like cellulosic, become commercially viable. Incurring those costs now would actually reduce the commercial viability threshold for the exotic sources of ethanol, as they become available. The arguments against importing ethanol to add to domestic production center around the negative point that the US would still be importing. However, several counter-arguments should be kept in mind: ? The proposed approach makes full use of domestic ethanol production capability, so no domestic enterprise is harmed. ? Importing from Central America, the Caribbean, and South America places our energy supplies in far less jeopardy than importing from Asia and Africa. ? The development of an additional lucrative cash crop would aid Latin American economies; in addition to being a good neighbor, the US should also see some relief with its drug and immigration issues along its southern border. ? Ethanol would be the first true alternative to oil, and having it developed commercially in sufficient volumes would offer some elasticity to the oil-pricing problem, and provide some leverage against oil price spikes | 2/18/14 |
Sulphates DATournament: berk | Round: Doubles | Opponent: The Walia Man | Judge: Shmikler, Fink, Fried MAN'S attempts to halt the greenhouse effect by cutting carbon dioxide emissions could make the world even hotter, scientists have warned. The latest research challenges the conventional wisdom about the best way to stop global warming: to burn less coal and oil and thus release smaller amounts of carbon dioxide into the atmosphere. Scientists say that, if fewer fossil fuels were burnt, there would be a reduction in the release of sulphur dioxide as well as of carbon dioxide - and their research suggests that sulphur dioxide has been keeping the world cooler than it would otherwise have become as a result of the Industrial Revolution. Professor Tom Wigley, of the Climatic Research Unit of the University of East Anglia, says in the current issue of Physics World that sulphur dioxide stays in the atmosphere for a much shorter time than carbon dioxide. Cutting both gases would thus remove sulphur dioxide more quickly. ''The first response of the climate system to a fossil-fuel cutback might therefore be a warming rather than a cooling,'' he says. Professor Wigley, one of the world's leading experts on climate, reached this conclusion after a new study of the role of sulphur emissions by a team of researchers at the Lawrence Livermore National Laboratory in California. Factories and power stations release thousands of tons of sulphur dioxide over land in the northern hemisphere by burning fossil fuels. Some of this falls back to Earth in the form of acid rain, and some wafts out to sea where it is converted into sulphates. Once over the sea, sulphates act as tiny particles for water vapour to condense, and so are important in the formation of clouds which block sunlight and keep the oceans cool. Without sulphates, fewer clouds would form and sea temperatures would rise. The suggestion was first made nearly 20 years ago, but with little evidence to support it. It was revived more recently, but researchers thought that sulphates could result from marine algae rather than industrial sources. So important is sulphur dioxide in the formation of clouds that the Lawrence Livermore researchers believe man-made emissions of sulphur dioxide could account for the fact that global warming since the Industrial Revolution has been less than predicted from known increases in carbon dioxide emissions over the past 100 years.''A 1C rise is indicated but we've only seen about 0.5C,'' said Dr Joyce Penner of the Lawrence Livermore laboratory. ''Man- made emissions of sulphur dioxide may explain why we haven't seen the magnitude of warming we expected.'' That’s independently a reason to negate since they’ll trigger their own impacts FASTER but even if you don’t buy that, Decreases in sulfur emissions means an increase in methane emissions. Gauci Our estimates of the combined effects of climate change, sulfate aerosol radiative effects, and SDEP (GHGAEROSDEP) on CH4 emissions show that anthropogenic SDEP may have been sufficient to have decreased the global wetland CH4 source to a level below preindustrial estimates by 10–15 Tg during the second half of the 20th century (Fig. 3). The combined effect of SO4 2 aerosols (cooling) and SO4 2-deposition (limiting methane production at the source by microbial competition) are predicted to offset the effect of GHG warming on CH4 emissions by 26 Tg in 2030 and by 15 Tg in 2080. In this scenario, CH4 emissions will exceed preindustrial emissions by 14 Tg by 2080. The influence of production and deposition of oxidized sulfur compounds through economic growth in North America and Europe between 1960 and 1980, followed by increases in the economic growth in South America, Africa, and (primarily) Asia, are responsible for this pattern. Beyond 2030, however, a decline is predicted in sulfur pollution because of anticipated cleaner technologies. Together with the additional effect of enhanced greenhouse warming, we predict this reduction in sulfur pollution will result in a rapid increase in CH4 emission (15 enhancement between 2030 and 2080) that may exacerbate climate warming during that time. Methane emissions guarantee a cycle of warming. Kaku Extend their impact, its going to happen faster with emissions reduction. Connor, Science Editor of the Independent London, 1990 Steve, Science Editor of The Independent (London), “Carbon dioxide cuts 'may heat up earth'”, The Independent (London), August 19, 1990, pg. 7 | 2/18/14 |
Survival of the Fittest NCTournament: anything jan feb | Round: 1 | Opponent: x | Judge: x This is a powerful response, but today’s evolutionary ethicist argues that it misses entirely the full force of what biology tells us. It is indeed true that you cannot deduce moral claims from factual claims (about origins). However, using factual claims about origins, you can give moral claims the only foundational explanation that they might possibly have. In particular, the evolutionist argues that, thanks to our science, we see that ought claims like “You ought to maximize personal liberty” are no more than subjective expressions, impressed upon our thinking because of their adaptive value. In other words, we see that morality has no philosophically objective foundation. It is just an illusion, fobbed off on us to promote biological “altruism.” This is a strong claim, so let us understand it fully. The evolutionist is no longer attempting to derive morality from factual foundations. His/her claim now is that there are no foundations of any sort from which to derive morality-be these foundations evolution, Gods will, or whatever. Since, clearly, ethics is not nonexistent, the evolutionist locates our moral feelings simply in the subjective nature of human psychology. At this level, morality has no more (and no less) status than that of the terror we feel at the unknown-another emotion which has good biological adaptive value. That’s the only way to make moral statements prescriptively valid. Joyce Moral inescapability is an elusive notion. Imagine the child asking why he mustn’t pinch his play mate. The parent replies “Because it’s wrong.” The child continues “But why mustn’t I do what’s wrong?” The parent might give an exasperated “Because you mustn’t!” It is the attempt to clarify the inadequate parental response that is the task of this chapter. Of course, there are all sorts of kinds of reasons that the parent might give: “If you pinch Violet Elizabeth, then she might pinch you back” or “...then she won’t play with you” or “...then you’ll be sent to your room.” All good (and possibly effective) prudential reasons. But prudence does, I shall argue, is not what underwrites moral prescriptivity. Regarding any type of prescription which can be justified on prudential grounds, we can always imagine an unusually situated or unusually constituted agent who “escapes” the prescription. Perhaps the child doesn’t want Violet Elizabeth as his friend, perhaps he doesn’t mind being pinched or being sent to his room. Or perhaps these costly consequences are things he has the power to avoid. In such a case what becomes of the injunction against pinching? On prudential grounds, it must evaporate. But moral proscriptions do not evaporate, regardless of how we imagine the agent situated. If it is not pinching, but torturing that is at stake, then there is no escaping. But the thought that torturing is always proscribed on prudential grounds is just silly. That it always is as a matter of fact is a case that might be made – but that it must be, even in situations where the philosopher gets to stipulate the costs and benefits (let’s say without breaking any laws of nature) is are nothing but groundless optimism. (Morality as a kind of prudence is discussed further in later chapters: §3.2 and §7.1.) Thus the standard is consistency with evolutionary tendencies. Strong evolutionary tendencies favor resource extraction. Penn: We humans, especially those living in industrialized nations, consume an amazing portion of the Earth’s available natural resources. Americans, for example, represent around 5 percent of the Earth’s population, and yet consume 25 percent of the resources, release 20 percent of the carbon dioxide emissions that contribute to global climate change, and generate almost 50 percent of the hazardous waste produced on the planet. How can we explain why people in industrialized countries consume so much? Americans consume so many calories from fats and sugars that obesity and diabetes have become major epidemics! The evolutionary reason for overeating seems straightforward: selection appears to have favored open-ended cravings for fats and sugars that were difficult to obtain for our ancestors; modern fast foods satisfy our evolved dietary preferences but remove the energetic costs of hunting, foraging, and processing the good. Our environmental impact, however, is not simply from overconsuming food and other resources needed for sustenance and survival. It is mainly from the pursuit of extravagant goods, such as fashionable clothes, luxurious cars, and massive homes (Durning 1992; Frank 2000; de Graaf et al. 2001). Why do people spend so much time and trouble pursuing resources that have no survival value? What is the appeal of buying expensive large automobiles, designer watches, fur coats, and following the latest fashion trends? To explain the evolution of conspicuous and extravagant traits in animals, such as a peacock’s elaborate plumage, Charles Darwin To explain the evolution of conspicuous and extravagant traits in animals, such as a peacock’s elaborate plumage, Charles Darwin (1871) proposed that they function to attract mates and repel rivals (i.e., they evolve through differential mating success or “sexual selection”). The problem has been to explain why traits that are handicaps to survival would be sexually attractive or increase status. Amotz Zahavi (1975) suggested that costly exaggerated displays enable high quality males to honestly advertise their quality to potential mates and rivals because only high quality individuals can bear the costs of the display. This “handicap principle” or “honest signaling theory” helps to explain the evolution of extravagant displays in animals (Zahavi and Zahavi 1997), and offers implications for many aspects of human behavior (Miller 2000). Interestingly, honest signaling theory was first suggested by the economist Thorstein Veblen (1899) to explain the excessive consumption by wealthy people. He coined the term “conspicuous consumption” to describe extravagant and ostentatious displays of resources that function as a competitive strategy to demonstrate wealth and social status: “Conspicuous waste and conspicuous leisure are reputable because they are evidence of pecuniary strength” (p 181). “Since the consumption of these . . . excellent goods is an evidence of wealth, it becomes honorific; and conversely, the failure to consume in due quantity and quality becomes a mark of inferiority and demerit” (p 74). Veblen also suggested why this process tends to escalate into increasingly wasteful displays of fashion and consumption: people instinctively acquire items to demonstrate group membership, but to rise in social status they must be able to display items worn by high status individuals, which in the modern world means wearing the expensive designer clothes, driving costly and wasteful cars, and buying large homes in expensive neighborhoods. If low status individuals are able to acquire the luxury items (or cheap copies) usually reserved to the wealthy “leisure class,” then the wealthy simply acquire more costly and ostentatious items to display their wealth. Veblen even attempted to place his ideas about conspicuous consumption within an evolutionary framework, but evolutionary biology was not yet a mature science. Michael Ruse, University of Guelph, Ontario, “Evolutionary Ethics: A Phoenix Arisen,” Joint Publication Board of Zygon, 1986. SM | 2/18/14 |
Will to Power NCTournament: anything jan feb | Round: 2 | Opponent: x | Judge: x The will to power is the best constitution of action. Action always aims at overcoming because any action is a drive for power. Katsafanas 2 So while a purely goal-directed act would seek to minimize resistances, a process-directed activity involves an active desire to encounter and overcome resistances. For if you aim to engage in some process, you must actually seek the objects upon which the process can be directed. This is why Nietzsche sometimes describes the will to power as “a will to overcome, a will that has in itself no end… a processus in infinitum, an active determin-ing” Or, as he elsewhere puts it, “the will to power can manifest itself only against resistances; therefore it seeks that which resists it” The link between the will to power thesis and the drive psychology should now beclear. Will to power is not an independent drive, but a description of the form that all drive-motivated actions take. This is why Heidegger was entirely correct to write that “ power can never be pre-established as will’s goal, as though power were something that could??rst be posited outside the will...The expression ‘to power ’ therefore never mean some sort of appendage to will. Rather, it comprises an elucidation of the essence of will itself.” To say that we will power is to say that we are motivated by drives.In sum, the will to power thesis describes the structure of drive-motivated actions. If an action is drive-motivated, then it aims at power. If, as Nietzsche seems to maintain,all actions are drive-motivated, then all actions aim at power.This entails that will to power is the constitutive aim of drive-motivated actions. For drives are motivational states that aim at their own continuous expression, and aiming at continuous expression entails aiming to encounter resistances to overcome. Theconclusion is simple: drive-motivated activities aim at encountering and overcomingresistance. The will to power precludes us from assenting to general state action – it underpins a consistent state of anarchy where individuals reject the state from influencing their lives. Martin Thus, the standard is the adherence to the Will to Power. Resource extraction is our greatest exertion of the will to power. Waters Katsafanas, Paul. “Deriving Ethics from Action: A Nietzchean Version of Constitutivism.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC. Boston University: 2011. | 2/18/14 |
Filename | Date | Uploaded By | Delete |
---|
Annie Wright (WA)
Apple Valley (MN)
Appleton East (WI)
Arbor View (NV)
Arcadia (CA)
Ashland (OR)
Bainbridge (WA)
Barbers Hill (TX)
BASIS Scottsdale (AZ)
Benjamin Franklin (LA)
Benjamin N Cardozo (NY)
Bettendorf (IA)
Bingham (UT)
Brentwood (CA)
Bronx Science (NY)
Brophy College Prep (AZ)
Brown (KY)
Byram Hills (NY)
Cambridge Rindge (MA)
Canyon Springs (NV)
Carpe Diem (NJ)
Cedar Ridge (TX)
Centennial (ID)
Center For Talented Youth (MD)
Cerritos (CA)
Chaminade (CA)
Charles E Smith (MD)
Christ Episcopal (LA)
Christopher Columbus (FL)
Citrus Valley (CA)
Claremont (CA)
Clements (TX)
College Prep (CA)
Collegiate (NY)
Colleyville Heritage (TX)
Coral Springs (FL)
Copper Hills (UT)
Cypress Bay (FL)
Cypress Falls (TX)
Cypress Ridge (TX)
Cypress Woods (TX)
Delbarton (NJ)
Derby (KS)
Des Moines Roosevelt (IA)
Desert Vista (AZ)
Dobson (AZ)
Dougherty Valley (CA)
Dowling Catholic (IA)
Dulles (TX)
Eastside Catholic (WA)
Elkins (TX)
Evanston (IL)
Evergreen Valley (CA)
Flintridge Sacred Heart (CA)
Flower Mound (TX)
Fordham Prep (NY)
Fort Lauderdale (FL)
Frontier (MO)
Gig Harbor (WA)
Grand Junction (CO)
Grapevine (TX)
Greenhill (TX)
Hamilton (AZ)
Hamilton (MT)
Harker (CA)
Harmony (TX)
Harrison (NY)
Harvard Westlake (CA)
Head Royce (CA)
Heights (MD)
Henry Grady (GA)
Highland (UT)
Hockaday (TX)
Houston Homeschool (TX)
Hutchinson (KS)
Immaculate Heart (CA)
Interlake (WA)
Isidore Newman (LA)
John Marshall (CA)
Jupiter (FL)
Kamiak (WA)
Katy Taylor (TX)
Kempner (TX)
Kent Denver (CO)
Kinkaid (TX)
Kudos College (CA)
La Costa Canyon (CA)
La Jolla (CA)
Lafayette (MO)
Lake Highland (FL)
Lakeville North (MN)
LAMP (AL)
Law Magnet (TX)
Leland (CA)
Leucadia Independent (CA)
Lexington (MA)
Liberty Christian (TX)
Lincoln (OR)
Livingston (NJ)
Logan (UT)
Lone Peak (UT)
Los Altos (CA)
Loyola (CA)
Lynbrook (CA)
Marcus (TX)
Marlborough (CA)
McClintock (AZ)
McDowell (PA)
McNeil (TX)
Meadows (NV)
Memorial (TX)
Millard North (NE)
Millburn (NJ)
Milpitas (CA)
Miramonte (CA)
Mission San Jose (CA)
Monsignor Kelly (TX)
Monta Vista (CA)
Montclair Kimberley (NJ)
Montville Township (NJ)
Mountain Pointe (AZ)
Mountain View (CA)
New Orleans Jesuit (LA)
Newark Science (NJ)
Newburgh Free Academy (NY)
North Crowley (TX)
Northland Christian (TX)
Oakwood (CA)
Okoboji (IA)
Oxbridge (FL)
Palo Alto (CA)
Palos Verdes Peninsula (CA)
Peak to Peak (CO)
Plano East (TX)
Presentation (CA)
Rancho Bernardo (CA)
Randolph (NJ)
Reagan (TX)
Ridge (NJ)
Riverside (SC)
Roseville (MN)
Round Rock (TX)
Rowland Hall (UT)
Sacred Heart (MA)
Salado (TX)
Sammamish (WA)
San Dieguito (CA)
San Marino (CA)
Saratoga (CA)
Scarsdale (NY)
Servite (CA)
Seven Lakes (TX)
Shawnee Mission South (KS)
Southlake Carroll (TX)
Sprague (OR)
St Francis (CA)
St Louis Park (MN)
St Margarets (CA)
St Marys Hall (TX)
St Thomas (MN)
St Thomas (TX)
Stoneman Douglas (FL)
Stony Point (TX)
Strake Jesuit (TX)
Stratford (TX)
Stuyvesant (NY)
Timothy Christian (NJ)
Torrey Pines (CA)
Travis (TX)
Trinity Prep (FL)
Trinity Valley (TX)
Turlock (CA)
University School (OH)
University (FL)
Valley (IA)
Valor Christian (CO)
Vashon (WA)
Veritas Prep (AZ)
Walt Whitman (MD)
Wenatchee (WA)
West (UT)
Westlake (TX)
Westwood (TX)
Whitney (CA)
Winston Churchill (TX)
Woodlands (TX)
Woodlands College Park (TX)
Wren (SC)